The Parable of the Berlin Wall: Barriers to Curriculum Development in Music Education

from Morning Watch: Educational and Social Analysis, 19/1-2, pp40-46 1991

I

The Parable

For the better part of the decade before I took my position at Memorial in 1981, I was engaged in Germany in the successful pursuit of a career as a tenor soloist. During those years I had the opportunity to work with many fine orchestras and choirs under some very talented conductors. Among the many places where I regularly performed was West Berlin. Fortnightly on Saturdays, the Wilhelm Gedächtnis church in the heart of the new city held a concert series of Bach cantatas which I was often asked to sing.

During my many trips to West Berlin, I regularly made visits to the East where sheet music was, by Western standards, extremely inexpensive. Since I purchased large quantities of music with Western currency, I became quite well known to the staff at the two best of the only three places in East Berlin which sold such material. We would have long chats about Western things about which they dreamed and they would ask what I had come to sing on this or that particular occasion. While all somewhat transient and superficial, our conversations were nevertheless a source of pleasure and enlightenment for me because I came to understand the East and the people.

On the very last visit I made to East Berlin, our chat took the usual track of inquiry into my concert schedule and where and when in West Berlin I would be performing. Then, for the first time, one of the staff said to me simply that she wished that she could come and hear me. Never before in my life had I been so wonderstruck by the freedom we enjoyed in the West. We were discussing this not more than a few minutes walk away from the concert venue and yet with these few words, the worlds between us became light years apart. There was no possibility at all of this lovely lady walking over to my concert because someone else had build a concrete wall between us. What ought to have been a few minutes walk was an eternity away, both physically and intellectually. I had no response for her!

II

As more recent events have shown us, this state of things in Berlin was an unnatural perversion imposed on the will of a people who fundamentally found it contrary to their nature. As recent events have also shown us, some of these people were not only content with this system, they had made their own way in it and were strong supporters of the tyranny. Party members enjoyed support and power at the expense of the many who had little or no opportunity to voice an opinion let alone put any contrary action into effect.

III

I would now like to draw what I see as the parallels to music education from this story. I see music education, particularly at the tertiary level, like the people in the East. Our legitimate efforts at curricular innovation are subjected to an inappropriate external control which has, through a now outdated style of vision, built a wall similar to the one in Berlin to restrain those of us in the educational arena from escaping their power in favour of a more contemporary vision of music education.

In order to discuss this I would first like to re-examine some of the notions attributed to the sociological construct of “professional” and show that following these rules, a strong case can be made for including educationists while excluding “musicians” as craftsmen. The importance of this construct shows that it can be used to challenge the control of knowledge currently claimed and exerted by music faculties on university campuses.

IV

Chasing an adequate definition of “professional” is a difficult undertaking. Barrow and Milburn (1990:249) are right when they suggest that professional “is a `hurrah’ word, one that teachers as a body lay claim to with an uncertain grasp”. They come closer to a workable beginning when they refute the notion by Hudson (1983) that “anyone is free to work as a teacher”. No-one ought to challenge the idea that we can be taught certain things by most anyone acting “as a teacher”, but as we understand teaching, in the more formal state-schooling sense, some are “empowered” by society while others simply are not. This surrogate role is not an unusual occurrence with any of the professions. Accepting for example that medicine may be considered a profession, a parent will admit to usurping the medical professional empowerment to diagnose and treat a variety of cuts and abrasions, measles and mumps. In other words, to act “as a physician” in certain situations is acceptable to society. To suggest that I operate on my neighbour’s son to remove a tumour, notwithstanding the fact that I may even know how to do it, would soon engage the authorities who are the guardians of this societal empowerment. Thus acting “as” a teacher does not in any real sense allow one to claim that one “is” a teacher. Furthermore, any contrary claims will not make it so!

Like “teachers”, other true professionals have as a first requirement for access to the professional label such as “doctor” or “lawyer” the completion of an appropriate degree from a recognized institution. This becomes a legal claim to employ the label usually through a recognised “qualifying association” such as the Canadian Medical Association, or in the case of teaching by provincial licensing authorities. This licence exists in order to confer a legitimate right to practice and also to control entrance to the profession.

A more comprehensive view of the teacher’s claim to professional status can be found in Impey (1982:483). Impey writes, “For my description I have utilized as an outline some of the characteristics that various writers use to define “professionals” but I am not taking these as ideal, just as a convenient framework. I have chosen the following five characteristics: (1) the knowledge base: a profession is founded on an area of knowledge in which members of the profession tend to specialize and is exclusive to them. (2) the service orientation…(3) autonomy (4) past and future consciousness: professionals usually try to improve their service by reflecting systematically on past actions and by looking ahead…(5) group solidarity. This is not an exhaustive list but I felt that other characteristics were less of a problem, for example, one of the characteristics I have left out refers to the control of entry qualifications and mode of entry to the profession; in the case of science teachers this is covered by GTC regulations”.

While there is not a total uncontended agreement with all or perhaps many of these characteristics, their combined puissance is, in my view, still overpowered by the single notion that school teachers have a social contract of empowerment without which they may not engage in school teaching. They are the architects of the schooling experience for our children and are socially empowered to act in that capacity.

V

Musicians are artisans. Some of them are very good ones at that. Like craft bookbinders and cabinetmakers, they ply their craft with knowledge and technique and often an expertise that can astonish the beholder of their work. But they are professionals only in the sense that that is what they do for a living. In music, for example, Kadushin (1969) studied the “professional self-concept” of musicians and concluded that often the notion of a self constructed identity as a musician was all that was needed to assert that one was, in fact, a musician. A more useful and thorough examination of the social processes by which one can claim to be a musician is explored in Roberts (1991a). Zolberg (1990:125) writes that, “Becker’s de-mystification strategy takes the form of a descriptive re-creation of how art process functions. By depicting artists as workers whose creations, far from being the result of mysterious forces, are the products of cooperative action by (often) nameless collaborators, he dethrones the aestheticist conception of fine art”.

But certainly the application of the characteristics listed above must fail to convince us that musicians can be considered “professionals”. The most important deficiency remains with the notion of social contract. The most prestigious positions for musicians are achieved, not on the basis of institutionalized qualifying standards or licensing, but on the basis of competitive demonstration of the artisan skill. We call it the “audition”. In fact, despite the availability of university degrees in classical music, working musicians are never in need of such degrees if they can really play. Other categories of music (such as folk, rock, pop, etc.) which are not represented within the university music scene, are no more confined to degree status than is the classical genre. While no-one ought to dispute that students in these university degree programmes are taught these artisan skills which are necessary for employment as a musician, the degree itself, has absolutely no importance at all except in one single arena – education.

VI

Music degree holders are eligible to enter the world of education not because they have specific skills in music, but because they hold a degree in an area of schooling. This makes the university music school the gate keeper for all of the music education profession. In order to appreciate the significance of this, it is important to review briefly the genesis of music in the universities. Music schools in the university setting grew from an established presence of scholars in musicology who were typically placed in history departments or more general humanities departments. A few philosophers also concerned themselves with aesthetics. Curriculum established by these scholars came from the “received” perspective (Eggleston, 1977). Eventually, they hired like-minded colleagues. Finally, even performance was added to the university offerings for credit. The curriculum was viewed as a representation of reality, that is, as knowledge presented to students as the essential nature of subjects or as fundamental understandings in a “received” perspective. Subjects became disciplines and achieved thereby a form of immortality along with their own form of self-justification. In music, as Small (1987) so rightly points out, the curriculum was established to study the established and acknowledged masterpieces of the art form. Music was cultural artefact – great symphonies, great operas, great concertos and great tone poems. The role of the university scholar was to establish rules by which these artifacts could be judged and assigned value. Students were taught the rules and learned to value those artifacts deemed appropriate. This stubborn tendency in the arts remains even today and is certainly clear in the recent paper by E.D. Hirsch, Jr. (1990:4/5) when he writes, “It is incumbent upon those of us who believe in art education to decide which artists and works of art should be known in common by all students”. Later he writes, “the task of art education in deciding upon a definite curriculum is simultaneously to raise everyone to a level of existing mainstream culture and to attempt to advance existing culture beyond its current level”.

In music education, this has traditionally been interpreted to mean that those of us in the know would select the best symphonies and concertos and operas for classes to learn about. This cultural hegemony in music education has been rampant and is still the mainstay of university music schools (Rose, 1990).

VII

As sociologists in the early 1970’s began to critically examine the curriculum of schooling rather than accepting it as a taken-for-granted changes began to occur. What gradually emerged was the notion of the “reflexive” perspective (Eggleston, 1977). In consequence, a limited rather than a universal view of the world prevailed. One of the main studies of the early seventies in the area of curricular knowledge happened coincidentally to be in music education. Vulliamy (1977) examined the British school music curriculum as a form of elitist knowledge. His main orientation was to examine the rationale for the absence of pop/rock music in the official curriculum. He reports on experimental curriculum projects where students are asked to compose music themselves rather than study about other composers’ music that “such an approach to music education involves a radical redefinition of what counts as music” (:23). Despite the criticism launched toward Hirst’s writings by some later scholars, Hirst was very clear about the nature of the arts altogether, an issue his critics tend to ignore. He writes (1974:158), “Art is not a natural given, it is a social product with its own role and function in the life of man”.

I would now like to return to Hirsch (1990), who I believe gives us clues which he has misinterpreted in his own paper. It is obvious that his intent is to show that the goal of arts education should be a hegemonic process of enculteration. This he sees as a “direct utility of art education” (:3). He writes, “no advocate of the arts should feel tainted or somehow impure in stressing the straightforward social utility of education in the arts. Indeed, the subject of utility, both for the individual as well as for society, goes to the heart of what is valuable in the arts”(1990:3). But as he leads us closer to the core of his argument, he writes, “The aesthetic values of sport, like the aesthetics of painting, are also instrumental values in the sense that they are satisfying to people and therefore not truly ends in themselves. They are ends for people”.

Now here seems to me to be the pivotal point at which in today’s world, he might have proceeded with a full exposition of how the arts and people are connected. Others have quite successfully constructed a more contemporary vision of what music is. Kingsbury (1984:52) for example concludes simply that “the concrete reality of music is social process. It is social process which gives music meaning, and it is this meaning which makes music what it `is’. Music is a category of social meaning”. Even more direct is this comment by Elliott (1989:12) who writes, “in short, because music is, in essence, something that people make or do, a people’s music is something that they are, both during and after the making of music and the experiencing of music”.

Musical knowledge must be viewed as process and not simply as cultural artefact. Small (1987:51) writes simply that, “it follows that whatever meaning there is in music is to be found in that act [of musicking] rather than in the actual works themselves”.

No-one disputes that there are symphonies by Mozart, operas by Wagner and concertos by Brahms. But what may be pursued is the relationship to music that is translated socially into an identity as a “musician”. Facts about man’s accomplishments are available to many in the form of artifacts. The craft of bookbinding is available in the world’s museum collections of beautifully bound tomes. That Kurt Browning remains the reigning world figure skating champion is available on videocassette. Despite the fact that this knowledge is generally available and is perhaps worth knowing, none of this knowledge will make the “knower” either a craft bookbinder nor a world-class figure skater. The fact that one might come to appreciate these forms as art forms of skill and beauty do not in any way contribute to an involvement with the discipline itself as a craft bookbinder nor skater. Music ought to be seen in the same light. There is nothing particularly wrong with knowing about musical artifacts, Bach or the Beatles. But to know music, is to be a musician.

VIII

Small (1987:176) writes of the social control that exists to define the world’s most worthy or best musics. He has stark words for music departments in the universities when he writes that, “the majority of university departments are still stuck in an exclusive concern with the past”. The artifacts and gestures of classical music remain the exclusive valued diet in university music schools (Roberts, 1991b). This is but one small corner of the world’s musics which music education curricula are growing to embrace. As long as the university music schools maintain their role as gate keepers to their own vision of what counts as music, music education will remained shackled behind the academic equivalent of the Berlin wall.

Of course, music schools solicit support from their graduates who have bought into their ideological position. These are the musicians, which, because of their degree status, become the exclusive pool of applicants for teacher certification programmes. The historical changes in curriculum perspective make it clear that these students have constructed a musician identity which is not concurrent with the multi-faceted reality that is facing them in the classroom.

If we accept Vulliamy’s charge that a change in school curricular repertoire to include other forms of music requires a radical redefinition of what counts as music, then the obvious goal of continuing education in music education must be to allow teachers to escape their chains of cultural reproduction. It is not the performing skills but the context and reification which bind these musicians. Music teachers need the performing knowledge to take advantage of students’ cultural capital and to foster their own understanding of the knowledge of performing in the cornucopia of musical genres available to today’s youth.

The degree to which our hands in educational programmes are tied to the old ways of the music schools will be indicative of the success we will ultimately meet in preparing professionals to meet these challenges. Our current system, if we accept the metaphor of the teacher as the architect of the schooling experience outlined above, has the stone cutter telling the architect the only allowable way to design a house despite a plethora of new building styles and materials. We ought to welcome the extent that the classically trained artisan can contribute to the process of music education, but in today’s world, it is no longer acceptable to have the artisan directing the professional.

Our wall, like that in Berlin, will hopefully soon fall and we will be able to offer a truly contemporary curriculum to the students in our schools.

International Theorizing in Music Education: The MayDay Group and Its Agenda

Presented at the International Society for Music Education
Pretoria, South Africa, July 17-25, 1998
[based on the author’s opening address:
Charles Fowler Colloquium on Arts Education,
April 18-19, 1997, University of Maryland, College Park]

Today, I want to do three things: first to introduce you to the international work and purposes of the MayDay Group; second to share some of the world-wide theoretical issues that have developed in our discussions and on which we are now working. Last, I will invite you to join our dialog, contribute to the work of our Group and participate in the kinds of symposia we hold. I’ll tell you about this at the end of my presentation.

Early in 1993, Thomas Regelski and I had a conversation about the isolation from each other of music education theorists. The more we talked to others, the more we found that they were not sharing ideas with each other frequently, systematically, and internationally; nor were they routinely taking advantage of the ease of communication that the internet provides. This was the condition just five years ago, in spite of the increasing numbers of new resources in the theoretical area of music education. New theoretical books were published by David Elliott, Bennett Reimer, Keith Swanwick, Robert Walker, Harold Fiske and others. In the US, a Philosophy Special Research Interest Group was approved in our national music educators association. The Philosophy of Music Education Review was being created for music education philosophers and a triennial international philosophy symposium was being established, thanks to Estelle Jorgensen’s hard work. The British Journal of Music Education was making its mark in theorizing of all sorts, led by Keith Swanwick and John Paynter, and Richard Colwell’s then-new Quarterly Journal of Music Teaching and Learning solicited and courageously printed critical articles. Australian, Austrian and Canadian journals accepted theoretical articles. The status of all this today is that the triennial symposiums continue, and all but one of the journals are still available. The Quarterly is now gone, but a new Finnish journal accepts theoretical articles in English.

Wonderful as all this was and still is for the most part, it was not enough. Although the leaders of these projects eagerly sought international voices, there was little evidence that these methods would get theorists in contact with each other frequently enough to allow them to compare notes, to keep each other informed and challenged, and to try out lines of thinking while manuscripts were still in draft form.

In addition, Tom and I recognized a growing need for better theorizing. In music education research the open critical review of research and theory once provided by the Bulletin of the Council for Research in Music Education and the Quarterly disappeared when Richard Colwell and Manny Brand left those journals as editors. The process of refereeing manuscripts for journals and conventions is not an open process, and there is no defense against the claim of an editor or convention program coordinator who says that there are too few good manuscripts or session proposals, or that they had to rush a critique into print before the original writer was offered a chance to respond.

What emerged from this need on May first, 1993, was the first meeting of what became the MayDay Group. We invited some of our nearby friends to come at their own expense to a weekend exploration of each other’s minds in Buffalo, New York. In addition, Keith Swanwick was gracious enough to come from England to participate. Some came because they were curious, others because they had something on their minds that they wanted to share, still others because had political agendas of one kind or another.

Since then, we have developed tentative solutions for the dialog problem and found people around the world who care that our profession is internally held to high critical standards. Our current members are professionally situated in Austria, Australia, Canada, Finland, Great Britain, Japan, Korea and The United States. Thomas Regelski and I founded the MayDay Group and continue to coordinate it. We have lost some members and gained others, but the Group has doubled in size to almost 60 in the five years since it was founded, almost entirely by word-of-mouth. [Since late July, the membership grew to 80 and Germany, China and South Africa can be added to the list of countries.]

The MayDay Group

The name of the MayDay Group will give you something of its flavor. This name was the informal reference Tom and I made to the people we invited to Buffalo in 1993, but it survived our consideration of several alternative names (some of them quite academic and stuffy) which tells me something of its relevance:

First: Our first meeting was on May 1, 1993. In European-American culture, May first is called May Day, a day when, traditionally, secret admirers leave bouquets of flowers at the doorsteps of people they care about. The people we invited to Buffalo care about music education.

Second: MayDay is the international distress signal. We think our profession is in distress, especially in the seven areas noted in our pamphlet, Action for Change in Music Education. We insist on being an international group. This lifts the discussions we have above the local and national politics of our profession and, at the same time, broadens the base of experience upon which we each can draw.

Third: Although MayDay is a springtime celebration of renewal and fertility in some cultures, it is also a date that was used to commemorate revolutionary action in some societies. Professional renewal and fertility are beneficial, I guess, and we as individuals find ways to “recharge our batteries”; but renewal for the profession without collective action is unlikely. We intend to move our agenda forward.

To act on our beliefs, we currently maintain three programs:

The first project, and the one closest to our mission, is our communication network/ We have maintained email contact since we started, and that is our primary means of interaction. Our web site was developed in May, 1997. It is updated periodically and on it you’ll find various kinds of content. You can use the web site’s “current members” page to send email to any member of the MayDay Group, or another page to access many international and national music education organizations’ web sites. We invite you to explore the rest of our web site, if only to keep an eye on us.

We also maintain a discussion list on the internet for members, to address comments and send information to the Group by email. This is a place where members will challenge each other and criticize the directions of the Group. Charles Keil, for example, started quite a series of comments by wondering when we theorists would ever put our ideas to work with real kids … to “put our tires on the road and make them SQUEEEEEL,” as he said it. Other members put similar challenges out, and we need to find answers to such questions.

Our second program is our weekend colloquiums, now held in Spring and Fall. A few weeks ago, in Dallas, we heard seven critical papers, five of them on David Elliott’s praxialism. David had drafts or abstracts of these papers in advance and responded to them in Dallas. In addition to these five, Pentti Maatannen of Finland and Paul Woodford of Canada criticized various aspects of philosophical method as applied to music education. Our next meeting will be in Toronto in October 22-25, when we will consider and expand upon Keith Swanwick’s analysis for the MayDay Group of the issues of cultural and social influences on music teaching and learning, the second issue in Action for Change…. On April 30, 1999 Patricia Campbell will host our colloquium in Seattle on how music education can affect culture, the third of our issues, and in October of 1999 we’ll meet at a place yet to be announced. To “make the tires squeal” we are devoting some of these two colloquia to direct applications and inviting the profession through various means. Our colloquium in 2000 will be in June in Helsinki, Finland, following the Philosophy of Music Education Symposium to be held that year in England. Except for 2000, twice-yearly colloquium topics on music education issues are planned well into the future. Check the events page on this web site for a schedule.

These colloquia couldn’t be simpler: We get a place to meet, and then we invite our members to come to an intense philosophical discussion of music education issues, usually with some invited presentations as discussion starters. We usually start on Friday evening and go at it until Sunday noon.

A third project is the publication by various means of longer theoretical papers. Some members’ beliefs — and an outline of our agenda for theorizing — are contained in our set of guiding ideals for music education in the pamphlet Action for Change in Music Education. It took about 18 months to develop. We are eager to see these ideals analyzed, informed with our best thinking and used as the basis for criticizing practice. I’ll have more to say about these seven ideals in a few minutes.

We have tentatively isolated these seven issues for critical analysis and are currently beginning a set of monographs that we call the Music Education Critical Analysis Series, or MECAS, to explore them; most of our weekend colloquia in the next five years will be on these issues, one by one. The Critical Analysis Series is intended to examine our assumptions, clarify issues arising from this examination and analyze both the issues and our beliefs critically. The first of the Series, a paper on Critical Theory applied to music teaching by Thomas Regelski, is on our web site; the second, on Music as Culture by Keith Swanwick, is on this web site, accompanied by several related papers. Our meeting in Fall 1998 in Toronto will be on that issue, no 2 in Action for Change ….

The Concerns of the MayDay Group

What keeps us going? Internationally, we see two broad needs, and these form the broad purposes of the MayDay Group. They’re printed in Action for Change… and they appear on the home page of our web site.

(a) to apply critical theory and critical thinking to the purposes and practices of music education, and

(b) to affirm the central importance of musical participation in human life and, thus, the value of music in the general education of all people.

The MayDay Group is all about how we bring what we do to consciousness. For years, many of us have felt the need for a better theoretical formulation of our work and worked separately to develop one. James Mursell, Charles Leonhard, Abraham Schwadron, Bennett Reimer, Murray Schafer, Edwin Gordon, Paul Farnsworth, Thomas Regelski, Keith Swanwick, David Elliott and other theorists gathered adherents around their views. Ancestries developed, such as the Mursell-Leonhard-Reimer sequence in America. Other pedagogical theorists focused on some segment of our profession: Sinichi Suzuki, Paul Rolland, Carl Orff, Zoltan Kodály, Heitor Villa-Lobos and many others come to mind. These people and their students worked to advance their ideas in practice. Max Kaplan, Christopher Small, Charles Fowler, Estelle Jorgensen, Robert Walker, Pentti Maattanen, Antoine Hennion, Wayne Bowman and others published extended ideas about music education theory, but stopped short of gathering adherents deliberately. Harry Broudy, Phillip Phenix, Maxine Greene, Francis Sparshott, Elliot Eisner, Howard Gardner and others had much to say about music education in their more general educational writings.

Theory development was also done in groups. Among Americans, Harold Abeles, Charles Hoffer and Robert Klotman published an excellent theoretical overview of the field. Malcolm Tait and Paul Haack jointly developed a music education theory. Still others pulled short works from many theorists into single collections. John Paynter in England, as well as Michael Mark in America, and he and Charles Gary, provided our current histories of ideas about music education. My edited 1988 book is a collection of American critical and theoretical papers, as was the National Society for Secondary Education’s 1958 yearbook, Basic Concepts in Music Education, and Richard Colwell’s update of it, Basic Concepts…II. We’ve had meetings to motivate theory formation, too. In America, Max Kaplan and Robert Choate put together the Tanglewood Symposium in 1967 and Ronald Thomas assembled thinking practitioners for the Manhattanville Music Curriculum Project. The Yale Symposium, the Ann Arbor Symposia, the Wesleyan Symposium and others fit here. In the Pacific, Gary McPherson, Toru Mitsui, Tadahiro Murao, Masafumi Ogawa, Susan Chung, Myung-Sook Auh and others regularly organize conferences and symposia on music education issues. Tore West, Heidi Westerlund and Pentti Maattanen in Scandinavia organize symposia there, as do Lucy Green and others in England. There are still others, of course, and I apologize to those I left off this list; it was accidental.

The point is that the MayDay Group is part of this theoretical dialog. What makes us distinct from national music education associations and the International Society for Music Education is that we intend that the dialog be continuous rather than periodic, and we intend to be critical of music education practice. That is, we intend to hold a point of view that music in education should be carried out by people critical of their own teaching and skeptical of their unexamined pedagogical habits. We want to support music education by being fussy about the ways in which we rationalize it.

An aside: It is disturbing to note that most of the names I’ve mentioned here were males, most of them white males with firm roots in western civilization’s musical traditions. For reasons I’ll mention in a few minutes, the western civilization business is doubly disturbing. Both are being corrected. As of July 1998, a third of our members are female and we have members in Asia as well as in Europe, North America and Australia. The MayDay Group has slowly added members, by invitation at first and now by an open door to those who can and will contribute to the dialog. The MayDay Group is eager to engage anyone who feels the urgency we feel about our profession, has the love we have for it and has sufficient interest in our work to examine both research and practice critically.

The MayDay Group Agenda

I’d like to turn now to the The MayDay Group’s seven guiding ideals, printed in Action for Change…. These are not principles, since they arise from our beliefs rather than from research. They are not exactly utopian conditions, although we’d all be better off if we were justified in observing them in actual music education practice. They are, like “good living” or “fine tone quality,” more or less fixed orientations for directing our professional efforts and judging the results.

The first ideal is about the kinds of musical action we should hold up as excellent.

1. Musical action that is fully mindful of musical results is the necessary condition of music-making and, therefore, of an effective music education.

Some music is about life — that is the best music, regardless of what tradition it comes from. Other music imitates music or musicians — composers call music “derivative” if it imitates other musicians’ styles; commercial music critics and jazz experts wish imitative performers would “find their own style.” In addition to life music and imitative music, there are sounds called music that are neither about life nor about other music — pencil music or finger-music. Technical exercises and some etudes fit here. Finally, there is “ear candy” — music-like sounds intended to feed the market demand based on fashion and simple appetites.

Here’s the point: Too few people know the difference. Too much mindless sound-making happens. Too many well-meaning people give too much credit for mechanical music making and over-produced performances. Too much emphasis is placed on music-related activity that seems creative and entertaining but leaves little behind in the person when the fun is over. Wouldn’t it be great to have students who take seriously what they do in music, people who remember from class to class what they learned in the last class, people who know what to fix in the music they are making, people who are eager to get to the next step in whatever they are working on in music? A critical approach to music making is an indispensible first step in producing this result. A critical approach is also a dominant and permanent attitude, not just a first step.

Critically reflective musicianship is what happens when a person intends to do something effective musically, and uses that intention as a standard to assess what actually happens. Independent musicianship develops in students when they truly have musical options — choices — and when they are encouraged to use them, demonstrate them, evaluate them and listen to others evaluate the results or use them. They adopt and adapt the music they make and hear, for their own musical purposes. They articulate their judgments and live by them. In ways such as these, and more, students become mindful of the musical results they are producing and become careful about making good musical life spaces for themselves and others. Values develop alongside knowledge and skill, and all these become the personal possession of each student and the collective possession of the society they are in the daily process of creating.

2. The social and cultural contexts of musical actions are integral to musical meaning and cannot be ignored or minimized in music education.

Music, the person, the society and the culture are interlocked members of a musical life, and therefore of music education theorizing.

Case 1: A young Hispanic girl’s letter to the editor was published not long ago in Rochester, New York. She lamented in her letter that her Anglo appearance separated her from her Hispanic friends. The letter was about how Hispanic she was: She ate the food, danced the dances, spoke the language, wore the clothes and listened to the music; but still she complained that she was not accepted fully.

This girl earnestly and deliberately used music and dance as ways to fit in with the group to which she wanted desperately to belong.

Case 2: An instrumental music teacher in Buffalo, New York attempts to motivate his students to practice at home. One group of his students reported that they were told by their church not to practice at all, much less practice at home. He investigated their report by discussing it with the students’ religious leader. The religious leader’s reasoning went this way: musical talent is a gift from God and it was arrogant to think that it could be improved by practicing.

The religious values of these students brought them into conflict with the musical and pedagogical values of their teacher.

Case 3: My wife and I visited a middle school in a suburb of London, England, where we observed students working to put melodies, harmonies and rhythms together in stylistically-authentic arrangements. They were making demo tapes as group projects. The teacher reported that a group from last year’s class went beyond the assignment: They called a producer at EMI records in London to pitch their demo tape, that is, to try to get EMI to produce it. They invited him to lunch. Not only did the producer agree to meet them for lunch and discuss their project, he even bought the lunch.

No — their song never was produced. But the kids lived some of the real-world context that provided both the basis and, in their case, the consequence of their classroom project.

Musical values extend beyond music for its own sake to these kinds of situations. Students sense this and long for it. They will live their musical lives in context, not in theoretical isolation or even in personal isolation. Choosing music for a wedding, deciding musical policies on a symphony orchestra board, selling grapefruit and candy to support the school musical theatre presentation, preserving a sensitive trumpet embouchure while playing skillfully in a marching band, applying for a government grant to make a music documentary video, buying CDs and music videos, selecting and sorting published music, building musical instruments, singing and dancing the traditions of one’s people — all of these contribute to and draw strength from some level of musical meaning.

Most of these examples are from the center of a limited set of white European-American musical traditions. There is a wider musical world, even in that set, and most of our students live in it, or will come in contact with it no matter where their 21st century lives take them. Aesthetic criticism often conflicts with, or fails to illuminate, real-world musical practices. We need a broader rationale, and we can empower our students better with a broader, better curriculum. We can put them in personal control of a broader set of musical choices and skills so that they can live well, musically, in the information age.

We can lead our students to value musical choices and gain musical skills, but can music teachers improve music in the communities around them? We think we must.
3. Since human musical actions create, sustain and re-shape musical cultures, music educators can and should formally channel this cultural process, influencing the directions in which it develops and the individual and collective human values it serves.

For me, human musical action — in the school and in the community — is the core of a professional agenda. Music is broad and deep enough to contribute to many uses and functions in life, but other musicians and their patrons are rationally focused on their own, unique interests: Symphony orchestra managers and performers want symphony patrons who know something about the music and will support the performers finanacially. Recording company producers want customers. Street musicians want donations. Barbershop quartet singers want an audience. Church musicians want to contribute to worship. Film music composers want to enhance the effect on the screen so that they can keep their careers going. Performing arts center directors, media policy makers and ministers of culture want audiences from clearly-defined segments of the population. Piano technicians and instrument repair people want customers. None of these is musically in contact with the whole, messy, heterogeneous population at the same time. Instead, they knowingly select their populations by type, or the populations select the providers by choosing the event or service that interests them.

The elementary and secondary school music teacher isn’t so lucky, and, ironically, herein lies music education’s power. In every classroom music teacher’s week s/he meets a community’s future lawyers, garbage collectors, teachers, carpenters, government officials, automobile mechanics, social workers and industrial tycoons; and roughly half of her week’s students are potential mothers and the other half are potential fathers. The future criminals are there, too, and so are some potential saints. We touch our students with music, even after they graduate, and through them we can improve the musical life of the homes and communities they will eventually create. Zoltan Kodály was right: We are teaching the grandchildren of the students before us, and that gives our work both a sense of permanence and a sense of responsibility. Only the music educator has a professional interest in the musical health of all of a community and all of its people — not the symphony orchestra board member, not the instrument repair person.

Providing opportunities and motivation for current and life-long music participation, opening the doors to musical alternatives unknown to our students and empowering our students with the capacity to reach across musical cultures easily can re-energize musical life. This can bring music participation back to a central place in these humans’ lives and in the communities they create for themselves. Given the stance of the music educator in communities, continuing music participation remains high on the theorist’s agenda.

Communities are full of musical institutions of all kinds, including those that are in schools, colleges and conservatories. All of these have musical policies. What about institutions?

4. The contributions made by schools, colleges and other musical institutions are important to musical culture, but these need to be systematically examined and evaluated in terms of the directions and extent of their influence.

Because most of us here work in schools or in some other sort of institution, we gather easily around the assumption that these institutions are wonderful, important, crucial to society’s success and flawlessly devoted to their clients. Other people, including our clients, sometimes, aren’t so sure. The MayDay approach is to examine our assumptions about institutions critically, using the institution’s own stated purposes, rationales and processes as a first level of analysis. We recognize that music teachers in institutions are both the agency for change and the gatekeeper for change — we can initiate change and we can prevent or permit change initiated by others or by social conditions. Critical analysis can help us to carry out this role wisely.

As an example of what music teachers can do from an institutional base, I’m going to talk about the USA for a minute: The American symphony orchestra as an institution has changed remarkably in 30 years. Then, our repertoires and public events were modeled after the great European orchestras. Now, American orchestras’ yearly repertoire has a higher percentage of popular music and a lower percentage of new music than before; soloists and conductors are chosen less for their elite credentials and more for their communication skills with audiences; a year’s programme of concerts and other services function more and more socially and educationally and less for connoisseurs; and the framing of the symphony’s presentations — the design of the events themselves — is more inviting and “user-friendly” than before. Almost all of this is in response to changing interests of the American audience.

Here’s the point: Much of today’s symphony audience and most of its policy makers in America were in elementary school and junior high school thirty years ago. What happened in their musical education? Tanglewood. All of the changes in the American orchestra I listed above were defined at Tanglewood in the summer of 1967 and encouraged by various means in American music education since then. It is arguably safe to say that, in the US, in one generation, music educators created the contemporary institution we call the American symphony orchestra. Now, thirty years after Tanglewood, we can recognize the effect of the values identified there — indirectly — on American institutions such as the symphony orchestra. Kodály was right again — we ARE educating the grandchildren of our students.

Music teachers caused this, but at the same time some teachers and symphony board members complain that popular taste has ruined the American orchestra. That is scapegoating. An aside: Although the analysis would be different, music teachers now working in America are products of the effect of popular music since Vatican II on Roman Catholic Church music and since the 1960s on the music in main-line Protestant churches. These issues have caused rancorous professional debates.

We must now react to these phenomena analytically, at a level above complaining and reacting badly to our own successes, or the ubiquity of popular music idioms. And we must be smarter about how we provide our students with personal defenses against the kinds of cultural imperialism that blinds people by their own appetite for “ear candy” — music not about life but about making money. Publishing companies, the mass media, the internet, the computer software industry, toy companies, retailers are after our students’ musical loyalties and our students must carve a musical life out of this jungle. Not only must we equip them handle this problem better, we can also work with these institutions and our schools to make a better jungle.

Without knowledge not usually found within music education, how can we do this? Good theorizing and good teaching take into account much more than musical information and skill. We must reach beyond our usual disciplinary boundaries in theorizing, social action, curriculum design and teacher education.

5. In order to be effective, music educators must establish and maintain contact with ideas and people from other disciplines.

Cross-disciplinary contact has intellectual benefits: It clarifies our perspectives, it keeps our field from becoming inbred and it gives us opportunities to interpret our interests to current and future leaders in other disciplines. Although this issue in its entirety will receive our analytical attention, I’m going to spend a minute only on the teacher education aspect of this. I’ve just told you about an American success with symphony orchestras. Now you can learn from an American mistake. I must hasten to add that I am virtually alone in thinking this is a mistake.

American music teacher educators made a serious error many years ago, I believe, when they gradually increased their students’ isolation from their future colleagues in other fields. Music students have always complained about the content in general courses in educational psychology, or educational history or sociology, or curriculum design, or testing. Their complaint was that they saw little direct relevance to music teaching in these courses. Because their complaint played into the economic and political interests of music departments — interests that have little to do with high quality teacher education — these topics were made part of music department courses instead and students were excused from the general courses that other teacher education students took together. To make matter worse department heads and music education professors bragged about these changes in national meetings.

What is happening as a result of this is that American music teachers aren’t included in local school policy making committees. We often have to fight our way into these discussions and we wonder why. We shouldn’t wonder. Simply put, this happens because teachers from other fields aren’t accustomed during college to seeing music teachers in such discussions. We music educators actively preserve our isolation from other teaching fields in colleges and universities while pre-service teachers in other fields meet collectively, in educational psychology classes, methods classes, sociology classes, student teaching seminars and on and on. This continues on the job. Our graduates in music pay a high price for their pre-service isolation.

In theorizing about such matters, the list of disciplines that form the basis for understanding music and people hasn’t changed much — psychology, sociology, anthropology, philosophy and the rest. The quality of on-the-job cross-disciplinary discussions is higher if those in the conversation can stretch their thoughts to these foundations that disciplines share. Too many cross-disciplinary discussions, and the projects that sometimes result from them, dance around on the surface. We in the arts too often are asked to decorate someone else’s discipline, rather than create a framework together that requires our shared students to connect an effective, engaging surface of some arts product with form, function and structure in two or more disciplines.

We seldom think about such things deeply. The MayDay Group approach is sympathetic to reflective teaching and learning, action research, and a results-oriented approach to our work. Thomas Regelski uses the term “methodolatry” to refer to the mindless use of teaching techniques. When music teachers merely imitate some conductor’s or other teacher’s habits, or implement without thought a clinician’s or a college professor’s recommended teaching techniques, teachers can easily blame these experts when their tricks don’t work in some middle school classroom. We can excuse our failures because someone else told us what to do and it didn’t work.

When we close the door of our classroom or studio and start to work with our students, our teaching is intensely personal. Each of us must shape it ourselves so that it is professionally successful for us and, more importantly, for our students. The student also must carry that success out of our classrooms in some usable form. That is where reflection comes in — we must look for evidence that this is happening. We must also be tough critics of our own success by asking, “Does it really amount to something for the student? What can my graduates actually do with what they’ve learned from me? If I changed my teaching, could they do more?”

Action research is one way to determine the general answer to that kind of question, and the teacher needs a working knowledge of more controlled research as well. Our research establishment is important, but it lacks a clear structure and has only a weak effect on practice.

6. The research and theoretical bases for music education must simultaneously be refined and radically broadened both in terms of their theoretical interest and practical relevance.

The International Society for Music Education and its publications, research sessions and commissions; the MENC’s Society for Research in Music Education, their Journal of Research in Music Education and Update; Brian Roberts’ Canadian journal; Richard Colwell’s and Manny Brand’s Quarterly Review of Music Teaching and Learning; Estelle Jorgensen’s Philosophy of Music Education Review; Frank Calloway’s leadership in Australia and Gary McPherson’s Australian journal; the launching of the British Journal of Music Education by Keith Swanwick and John Paynter; Kurt Blaukopf’s Institute for Music Sociology in Vienna; and more — all of these were established within the professional lives of some of us in this room. We have talked with, worked with, or are, the people who shaped the ways our research effort connects with our profession. However, this connection has not yet been made.

Here’s why: Most large fields — medicine, psychology, social work, management, even manufacturing — recognize at least three different but intentionally articulated levels of research activity: Let’s call them basic research, engineering and technology. Researchers at one level ground their work on other work at the same level, but they also use findings of researchers at other levels. A person who is working in technology knows the engineering research related to what he or she is working on, and may even know the basic research on which the engineering is based. To do anything else would be a waste of time and resources. The rare accidents that produce breakthroughs are remarked upon just because they are rare. Most research is deliberate, methodical work.

Perhaps because of the youthfulness of our research, we call every project that gathers and analyzes data research … period. We have not systematically made clear a research project’s relationship to other levels of research much less its relationship to practice. In my view, this is the first task — categorizing our research efforts by the type, source and consequence of research problems and findings.

Here’s the point: Once we know where a project fits in an articulated, multi-functional research structure, an adequate research criticism can be more clearly applied to specific projects. Research agendas become communicable. There is a sound basis for judging a project innovative rather than declaring that merely clever projects are seminal, which we do too easily. The rationale for the research project and the dissemination of findings occur in a more unified research context. And appropriate research criticism can be based on best practice for the type or category of the project — best practice in the scientific principles that stretch across disciplines, not just those in music education. The political challenge is to recognize that good criticism will improve practice in research as well as in teaching. All of it must be good and all of it is important to the success of our enterprise.

One caveat about research and teaching, and closer to critical thinking in education: We’re fond of the myth that teaching is scientific. William James started this myth unintentionally a century ago, but he warned against the deliberate construction of teaching behavior from science. For him and for us, the creativity of teachers — what Elliott Eisner called “educational imagination” — was and is the bedrock for our profession’s effectiveness. Pestalozzi, Froebel and other pedagogues, even Comenius, had a clear view of the extent to which teaching should or could be scientific. John Dewey, a student of James’s, had this clear view as well. Great teachers in all generations practice the art but may be reluctant to analyze their practice. That is for others, they usually say. To turn that around is a mistake: Science is analytical but does not directly create practice without some engineering in between.

We can create a better sense, however, of how the science and the art of teaching can inform each other, and we can’t do that by maintaining the myth that the two are combined in our field. The confused meanings of the collection of effort we currently call research must be sorted out first. When the classroom door closes and a teacher starts to work with students, the teacher is neither controlled by research nor worried much by that fact, and that’s understandable. We can do better.

All of these matters culminate in educational plans and policies that directly affect music teaching and learning. Primary among these is curriculum.

7. An extensive and intensive consideration of curriculum for music education is needed as a foundation to greater professional unity and must be guided by a sound philosophical process.

These days the buzzword is policy, mainly policies that shape curriculum, assessment and educational reform. National curriculums and national tests, common in Europe and Asia, are new in the USA. Keith Swanwick spent a busy weekend a few years ago preserving some musical sanity in Britain’s national music test. Michael Greene, Paul Lehman and others spent a busy few weeks pushing the US Congress to see arts education as a national priority.

But curriculum decisions are made closer to home. All of us are asked to shape educational plans and to communicate these plans through some sort of curriculum document. We must do this better. We must form the habit of using a tough philosophical approach to deciding how we are going to spend our time with our students. We must apply sound curriculum development processes, and we must base broad instructional decisions on warranted musical, psychological and sociological principles as well as on action research. If we do, we can speak more authoritatively about our decisions. Our beliefs, ideas and actions will begin to form a unified system that makes sense, not only to ourselves but also to others.

In countries represented so far by the MayDay Group, local control of school policy varies. In America local control is held sacred. Where local options exist, adopting national standards locally, or accommodating local programs to them, must not be done mindlessly.

Many curricular issues must still be resolved critically, and the content as well as the sequence of it must be critically reviewed before a program can be built to implement the curriculum. In this ISME conference, the wordUbuntu has a nice ring to it, but its meaning raises issues of what actual plans to make for students when school opens about cross-cultural musical understanding; multiculturalism; interdisciplinary integration; race, ethnicity, gender, religion, class and the politics of recognition through music; the role of religious music in government schools; musical subcultures like Afro-pop, reggae, salsa, ska, hip-hop and rap; the inclusion of special learners; cultural institutions and their roles in public education; etc. At a very basic level, there is a pressing theoretical issue: the teaching of musicianship through performance lacks a clear rationale — we do it but we can’t explain it enough to criticize it, even to ourselves.

We cannot merely continue to rationalize our own professional habits by claiming that they are licensed by the habits of some remembered musical ancestors. Those who were excellent were likely very reflective about their work, but we missed that when we were their students. Doing things out of habit only leaves our teaching actions and our students’ learning in our classes bereft of thought and lacking in conscious articulation with other musical content. The curriculum is our plan for helping our students achieve the high standards of a good, mindful, empowering musical life and we don’t criticize our plans well at all. The curriculum is the conductor’s score for the opera we call our music program. If we can’t analyze it and criticize it, we can’t improve it deliberately much less “conduct” effectively from it.

In summary

The challenge for the profession is clear. As you’ll see in a minute, we must equip ourselves and the next generation of music teachers for the fight of our lives. And curriculum and its related assessments, whether defined at the national, province, state or local school levels will be the battleground.

Before we get to the professional challenge that has emerged from this five years of MayDay Group work, let me summarize what I’ve said so far. Here’s a one-sentence version — a bottom line — of each of the MayDay Group’s action ideals:

1. Critically reflective music-making is basic to music education.

2. Consideration of music’s social and cultural contexts is integral to good theory and practice.

3. Music teachers can influence cultural change.

4. Schools, colleges and other musical institutions affect musical culture, but need critical evaluation.

5. Research and study of music teaching and learning need an inter-disciplinary approach.

6. The knowledge base of music educators should be both refined and broad.

7. Curriculum considerations are basic and should be guided by a critical,philosophical approach.

We are now systematically exploring these seven issues, articulated further in Action for Change…. Some MayDay Group members are exploring these philosophically. Some are using these as discussion points in graduate and undergraduate seminars. We hope you will, too.

Can anyone organize the kind of intense weekend colloqia we have? Of course. But, we find it important to cross national boundaries because doing so reveals how localized much of our thinking and rationalizing is. An international group puts our localized concerns in better perspective, as we know from ISME, and we learn from each other’s varying national successes and failures. At the beginning of my talk, I listed this and two other MayDay Group programmes to expand the dialog and engage the profession, and we hope you will discuss your views on this, or your desire to be part of our network, with me or other MayDay Group members here.

We are eager to help groups to duplicate the MayDay weekend experience in their regions, so others can have the intellectual benefits of serious thought on a theoretical level. There are some simple ground rules and Tom Regelski or I will be happy to work with any group that wants to explore a weekend of critical thinking as a kind of renewal. Our internet site has more. Its address is:

Welcome to the MayDay Group website

We have many questions as you can see by our pamphlet, Action for Change… , and each person in the MayDay Group develops well-considered answers for some of them. The groups that meet here and met in the Commissions last week have questions, too, and so do our students. Asking them fruitfully and seriously, as our best theorists do throughout their lives, is serious business. The MayDay Group and its work are not for the faint of heart.

The challenge ahead

I’ve given lots of thought to the internationality of the MayDay Group. I’ve been both pleased and surprised that the issues we are raising resonate across national borders so easily, and resonate with music teachers I talk with from many parts of the world.

After I got over being pleased and surprised, I got alarmed. The only conclusion I could support with the facts is that the school-based preservation system for music — at least in the industrialized world — is headed for serious, systemic trouble. That’s big stuff. The knowledgeable music educators of the MayDay Group sense that something’s wrong. MayDay Group folks in Austria, Australia, Canada, China, England, Finland, Germany, Japan, Korea, South Africa and the US — all firmly parts of “the industrialized world” — are in touch not only with their country’s professional trends but also what’s happening in other countries. We are editors, authors, music teachers at all levels, national research leaders, policy makers and organizers of symposiums and colloquiums. We are also teacher educators who listen to hundreds of stories from the field each year and have watched it for decades.

If music education is in trouble at the systemic level (or even if there is some equally disturbing alternative explanation for the MayDay Group’s international appeal) then we must immediately begin to draw folks into action in large numbers or risk — what?

Perhaps, we risk abandoning music education to some cultural processes that represent disturbing futures:

…to cultural processes such as the mass media that demand too little of general education,

…to cultural processes such as advertising that convince people to buy musical products that diminish rather than expand human musical potential,

…to cultural processes such as many government leaders’ political interests that push us back to a tribal, xenophobic approach to musical living, when the information age moves us in just the opposite direction, and

…to cultural processes such as retailing and commercial broadcasting that indoctrinate us with the commercial view: that musical insights should be no deeper than one’s childhood appetites and no wider than the personal borders of one’s convenient life-space.

For these reasons, we must strengthen the MayDay Group approach, expand the reach of these ideals, and take our concern for critical thinking to the grassroots. We must help each other to use our own countries’ various and varied successes in the struggle for human musical empowerment. Furthermore, we can and must use information-age processes to do it. That is the MayDay Group agenda.

When teachers believe in what they’re doing, can articulate the ideas that link belief with action, and can demonstrate these beliefs through the musical actions of other people (their students) then we can have a more powerful effect on music in our various societies. Successful music education is what we all stand for. The MayDay Group feels an urgency in this purpose, and we don’t have much time.

Critical Theory and Praxis: Professionalizing Music Education

Critical Theory is not just any philosophical critique. It is a prominent and well-grounded theoretical approach that stems from the “Frankfurt School” of social and political thinkers, philosophers, art critics, and psychologists early in this century in Germany. To thus distinguish Critical Theory from other species of critical social theory and from “critical thinking” in general, it will be referred to herein as a proper noun. Theorists such as Max Horkeiner, Walter Benjamin, Otto Kirchheimer, Friedrick Pollock, Leo Lowenthal and, more famously, Theodor W. Adorno, Herbert Marcuse, Eric Fromm, and Jurgen Habermas are all considered to be members. Critical Theory has been a major inspiration for the agenda of the MayDay group because it offers considerable practical implications for the theorizing of musicians and music educators.

The following is an informal introduction to Critical Theory. Because it is mainly intended for web site readers, most sources and notes have been intentionally excluded and examples and parenthetical comments have had to be included in the body of the text. Formatting is also kept basic. One convention will be the use of double quotes around words, expressions and ideas that function almost as code words for certain taken for granted kinds of received knowledge. The use of single quotes is reserved, then, for coined words, or for attaching the sense of “so-called” to the expression in question. The essay provides in particular a theoretical background to help clarify and place in a larger context the ideals stated in the agenda of the MayDay Group. However, it represents only the views of its author, one of the co-founders of the MayDay initiative, and admits of the possibility that other members may well have other premises behind their support of the MayDay agenda. Examples included to clarify certain points are naturally drawn from the author’s personal experience which is mainly in the US.; members from other countries will no doubt be able to furnish inst ances that are more applicable to their nations or regions.

In order to unify this rationale, several key themes are traced through extensively changing contexts of relevance and importance for the professional conduct of music education — in public schools and higher education, as well. It needs to be mentioned that any “critical” theory will be critical of any number of cherished paradigms. The criticism presented in this essay, however, needs to be understood as a critique in the positive and constructive sense encountered, for example, in good one-on-one musical instruction, rather than as negative and destructive in nature or purpose.

Depending on the font, a hard copy the body of the text will run about 30+ pages. The bibliography should not be considered as final or definitive because it will grow as members add relevant, briefly annotated contributions. Thus it will be useful to continue over time to consult it. Various technical terms are defined in context. It will be useful to take note of them when they are introduced because they will be used later on without further elaboration.

The essay is organized into sections, as follows, plus a brief summary and conclusion:

I. Traditional Theory: Scientific Positivism and Technicist Rationalism. The section below outlines the inherent problems created by the empiricism and rationalism of the Enlightenment — an important example being claims made for a “what works” technology of teaching.

II. Critical Theory. This section provides the basic “critique” of the traditional theory outlined in the first section. It analyzes the problems of an uncritical acceptance of claims to absolute truth and objectivity. Instead, it points out the need for “critical educators” — teachers (including university professors) who possess critical consciousness and use critical knowledge.

III. Origins and Problems of Uncritical Subjectivity. Though the life-world is situated and subjective in important particulars, uncritical subjectivity is shown to be an unsuccessful antidote for unwarranted objectivity, particularly in connection with an almost religious but unwarranted belief in so-called “good methods” and the resulting but false assumption that such methods guarantee “good results.” A distinction is made between “what works” misunderstood as mere practicability of methods, and the need to judge “what works” against standards provided by a warranted and functionally designed curriculum.

IV. Curriculum: Ideology versus a Phronesis of “Good Results.” Negative aspects of various ideological influences — both from outside and from within music education — are presented. The need for “ideology critique” on the part of teachers is argued and a curricular theory of teaching as praxis is developed in terms of an ethical criterion of promoting “good results” for students as a result of their musical schooling. “Good methods,” in this argument, are seen only in connection with “good results” qualified in terms of “action ideals” by a curriculum promotes personal musical agency.

V. Critical Theory, Research Theory and Teaching As and For Praxis. Change agency through teaching as action research is a condition of “critical teaching,” as is the need to draw upon basic research theory. The difference between “standards of praxis” and (mistaken notions of) standard or uniform practice is explained and points to a professional community of shared standards for guiding individual praxis. A praxial theory of music and musical value leads to the conclusion that teaching as praxis means teaching for praxis — i.e., teaching must bring about the ability and desire on the part of students to engage in music is a praxis that is “basic” to the life well-lived.

VI. Summary, Conclusions and Bibliography. A brief final section summarizes the ideas and provides links to a selective, annotated bibliography on Critical Theory and its applications to music education.

I Traditional Theory: Scientistic Positivism and Technicist Rationalism

Scientism

Empiricism, the basic paradigm of science, came into prominence during the 18th century intellectual and philosophical activity known as the Enlightenment. It holds that knowledge is gained only through the senses. Positivism (sometimes called logical empiricism, scientific empiricism, or scientific positivism) takes empiricism to an extreme by claiming that whatever cannot be verified by sensory experience (as observable ‘positive’ knowledge) cannot be explained, is unknowable or unreliable, and is thus not true knowledge. Positivists argue that the scientific method is the only source of valid, objective knowledge about reality — a claim labeled scientism by critics, including Critical Theorists. Scientistic positivism, in sum, holds that non-scientific claims to knowledge are meaningless, misleading, subjectively variable and thus capricious and dubious.

In use, positivism has faith only in the scientific quantification of ‘objective’ data and the corresponding use of statistics to state “laws.” The laws thus “discovered” in nature are used to make predictions: laws are “true” (i.e., scientific, objective, valid, reliable, ‘positive’) to the degree that predictions turn out as the laws forecast. Positivists hold that irregularities not predicted by present laws will eventually be covered by better, more comprehensive laws as they are discovered. Scientistic positivism has also traditionally rejected as meaningless (in the sense explained above) statements in the social sciences, arts, and humanities about the qualities or activities of “mind” and human subjectivity. In particular mentalistic, subjective states such as ideas, intentions and feelings are denied or devalued. Scientific behaviorism, for example, is a key example of this tendency and thus explains all human consciousness in terms of observable behavior. It excludes reference to (covert) mental events or states, or to the subjectivism of introspection of any kind, and in radical form it even denies the existence of mental states. Thus words such as “feeling,” “choosing,” “intending,” etc., are held to have no objective referents; their “meaning” (a condition that positivists in general have trouble explaining) is “seen” only in reference to overt behavior or dispositions for overt behavior.

In the physical sciences, positivism results in laws and predictions about natural “things.” Its results permit control of these things through technology and rationalized or scientized ‘management techniques’. Despite the important difference between “things” and people, most social scientists have tried to gain status as “scientists” by modeling their research on the positivist assumptions and practices of the physical sciences. Whatever the importance of such “basic research” theory, it is easily abused when mistakenly applied as law-like technologies of human functioning (e.g., social, economic, political or learning “theory” acted upon as “fact”). It is worth noting here that because it is modeled on the assumptions of positivistic-oriented social science, the preponderance of empirical research done in music education is clearly neo-behaviorist and thus positivist in its assumptions, practices, and results. Despite its complexities, human behavior is seen as ultimately responsive to statistically determined natural laws by this particular group of empirical researchers in music education and by positivists in the social sciences in general. And, it follows, what is predictable is ultimately controllable through rational means, systems and ‘standards’.

Technicism

Rationalism, the belief in reason as a source of reliable knowledge, also came to full flower during the Enlightenment. Originally the use of reason emphasized by Enlightenment thinkers was opposed to “authority” or “revelation” as sources of knowledge — in particular, the authority of the Church and of kings. The Enlightenment thus brought Western civilization out of the “Dark Ages” and initiated the “modern” era in history and the associated paradigms of what today is called modernism.

However, empiricism and rationalism converged during the Enlightenment in certain ways that excluded other possibilities. These directions ultimately led to: (a) the rise in the scientific method for determining valid knowledge; (b) the rise of technology and the resulting paradigm of technicism and its uncritical faith in “what works” kinds of “techniques” for applying such supposedly objective knowledge to solving human problems; (c) and, above all, the belief in the rational perfectibility of society through just such ‘management techniques’ or ‘methods’. Thus, as shall be illustrated below, when scientistic assumptions are applied to education, learning is assumed to be subject to objective and invariable laws referred to by the misleadingly benign term “learning theory.” And when technicist inspired rationalism applies such laws as “what works” techniques, teaching comes to be considered a technology of methods by which the learning process of learners is controlled. Teaching thus becomes a technicist undertaking rather than a professional praxis.

In the next section scientism and technicism and the “false consciousness” that results from blind acceptance of the positivist-modernist ideology of scientific-technical ‘progress’ are contrasted to the “critical consciousness” advocated by Critical Theory. Such a critique reestablishes the fundamental importance of the kind of personal agency that is situated — a condition that is central to both teaching as a professional praxis and to music as a human praxis.

II Critical Theory and Praxis: Professionalizing Music Education

Critical Theorists have been critical of the scientism and technicism that have resulted from the misuse of the empiricism and rationalism bequeathed by the Enlightenment. While seeing empiricism and rationalism as initially positive developments, Critical Theorists identify an inherent and unresolvable tension between these twin strands of what has come to be called modernism. While not wishing to overthrow modernism altogether (as in the case with other theories critical of postmodernism), Critical Theorists such as Habermas conclude that misapplications of rationalism and empiricism (e.g., rationalized political theories such as communism; technicist teaching “methods” and scientistic “learning theory”) have produced largely negative results. These theorists observed first-hand the extremely negative results of modernism seen during and after World War One, the world-wide economic “Depression,” and as a result of the rise of Nazi Germany and World War Two. In fact, the latter necessitated their departure for the United States for the duration of the war. Even after their relocation they noted critically that science and technology had produced negative results that would long outlast this or that war — for example, the hubris of the technocrats who designed, and the blind credulity of the passengers who sailed on, the supposedly unsinkable, but nonetheless ill-fated Titanic; or, more recently, environmental and ecological problems of industrialization.

Loss of Freedom

They argued in particular that the average person unwittingly forsakes his or her freedom by uncritically having faith in false claims that scientism and technicism promote rational economic planning and thus predictable progress towards a free, compassionate and perfect world. Such ultimate progress clearly has not happened; for example, who among us feels they live a happier more fulfilling life than, say, the Amish people? And the “average” person is generally skeptical of the claims made for modernism — a disappointment and frustration that is, for example, reflected in the tidal wave of both religious and secular conservatism worldwide and in various forms of social ‘unrest’. Nonetheless, people nonetheless continue to have uncritical faith in science and technology. The corresponding unwillingness or inability to take responsibility for their own lives is seen, for example, in their manipulation by media-driven values, “taste-makers,” cult leaders, and ‘movements,’ ‘systems’ and ‘institutionalized’ groups of various kinds. In this view, people everywhere can generally be described as, in the words one analyst used to describe the situation in the United States, a “nation of sheep.” In sum, unfreedom alone has progressed.

Similar conclusions are also reached by postmodernists, a diverse group of thinkers who point out the limitations and social situatedness of reason and science and thus argue that modernism has or should come to an end. Despite their basic agreement on the negative results of modernism, postmodernism and Critical Theory are critical of each other. Critical Theorists such as Habermas hope to reform or repair the misapplications of rationalism and empiricism begun in the Enlightenment. Postmodernists, pointing on the other hand to the ‘breakdown of modernity’, wish to ‘deconstruct’ the absolute and objective truth claims of reason and science in favor of other ways of understanding, guiding and empowering human action.

Critical Theorists complain, thus, that people have been misled into a false consciousness that blindly accepts science as the only source of true knowledge and to the belief that rational (technicist) ‘social planning’ can lead us to the ‘good life’. The ‘masses’ uncritically accept modernist claims that all human problems can be solved through technological, socio-scientific ‘management’ of society, the economy, the political process, the natural resources, and human resources involving the institutions of medicine, education and even entertainment. Thus, for Critical Theorists, scientism has led to a technology for both controlling physical things and human nature. It has denied subjectivity by idolizing false claims of objectivity and thus has become the vehicle for manipulation by ideologues who have brought a variety of crises and suffering to modern life by imposing their own beliefs and vested interests as being in the interests of all people. The result has been the political, social and cultural subjugation of people who are denied the empowering knowledge and social conditions for becoming the authors of their own histories.

Even worse, Critical Theorists conclude, people have succumbed once again (i.e., as was the case before the Enlightenment) to various authoritarian personalities and institutions. Thus they allow political demagogues, cult leaders, politicians, scientists and, yes, even school administrators, teachers and professors to mislead them with false and deceptive ideas of ‘objective’ truth and ‘absolute’ beauty as leading to the good life. So thoroughly have people accepted their new ‘chains’ that, not unlike Plato’s prisoners in the famous “Allegory of the Cave,” they prefer their unenlightened illusions to the full light of day and thus exhibit a fear of freedom that is the result of forsaking personal responsibility for their own lives.

Critical Theorists, then, are critical of the worship of objectivity because “facts” are never impartial or unprejudiced and science is therefore never completely value free. And these theorists are particularly critical of the scientistic misuses of empiricism to deny or otherwise control human subjectivity. Thus they have been centrally concerned with the misuse and abuse of reason in social, political, economic and ethical theories; that is, in all systems of thinking and functioning that deny personal freedom and personal responsibility. They point out that empiricism and reason have been turned back on themselves and have become the unreason of scientism and technicism.

Critical Theorists thus denounce any theory that leads, however indirectly, to practices that “disempower” human beings by taking away their own capacities for personal reason and judgment, and any theory that takes away people’s control over their own lives as agents who are personally responsible for their own being and becoming more fully human. They point to the dangers of uncritically applying totally abstract, merely “academic” theory directly to human problems. Such “academic” knowledge amounts to what Aristotle called theoria. Its danger resides in its claims to be value-free, for-its-own-sake, and thus “objective” and “true.” In the view of Critical Theory, such knowledge is never value free and, because it is influenced by a controlling ideology, never simply for-its-own-sake. For example, in Aristotle’s time, theoria existed to be contemplated by “free men” (not women) in the leisure time made possible by slaves, and modern researchers exchange their findings in return for professional advancement and economic gain. In fact, one criticism of positivism in the social sciences (that includes, I would argue, positivist research in education and music education) is that the resulting “journal science” contributes mainly to tenure and other career-advancement, not to concrete human betterment or to basic theory. The value of what today is called pure research is said to be its contribution to our theoretical understanding of the world as it seems to present itself to us. Such theory can sometimes guide action, but cannot by itself determine what “goods” such human action should serve. Thus Critical Theorists are keenly alert to the likelihood in modernist thinking for scientistic and technicist misappropriations of theory as direct “methods” and “techniques.”

Change Agency

In addition to their critique of the scientism and technicism of modernism, Critical Theorists also have a constructive agenda for change. Rather than rejecting science and reason altogether as postmodernists tend to do, Critical Theorists propose to reform or repair what they see as the mess modernism has made of the Enlightenment’s otherwise good potential — its agenda for jointly employing empirical knowledge and reason to improve the pragmatics of human life. They seek to actualize the heretofore unrealized potential of the Enlightenment for good. Their objective is to do so in ways that empower people to use their own reason to take more personal control of their own destinies rather than being manipulated by impersonal technologies directed by or toward rational, scientistic control of human action. In this “critical” view, human meaning is not “caused” by so-called objective, natural laws or impersonal, value-free, outside forces. For Critical Theory the “meaning” that constitutes the “good life” is internally caused, created or constituted by individuals situated in their own life-world — a situated life experience that is the result of both personal and social intentionality and that therefore involves communication with others. “Meaning” then is personally constituted within socially situated conditions; it is not handed around, passed on ready-made, or discovered “out there” in the world by science as ‘given’ by the laws of the universe. Each person is an agent and, by definition, an agent acts so as to achieve personal goals, needs and intentions that are necessarily situated in a context that has its own social, political, economic and even physical meaning and conditions. According to such situatedness, then, individuals function as autonomous agents who are the “cause” of their own personal meaning (or lack thereof).

Critical Theorists are thus interested in the pragmatics of personal or critical knowledge. Such knowledge is the result of critical consciousness — the perpetual awareness of the criteria and conditions argued by Critical Theory. Being thus critically aware of modernist abuses of science and reason, critical consciousness provides a properly warranted source of agency in personal affairs and serves as a warranted source of change in human affairs such as schooling. Such agents understand that scientific knowledge can only help people understand “things” as they are and that science can never tell them what ought to be the case. Thus any question concerning what ought to be is unavoidably a question of values that requires critical knowledge put into practice according to very ethical values and other philosophical criteria that science claims to avoid.

In schools, teachers who are empowered with critical knowledge and critical consciousness become critical educators. They help their own students rise to a level of critical consciousness and knowledge that empowers them to be more effective agents of their own personal histories. In the case of music education this would involve developing in students a critical consciousness of, for example, the economic imperatives of institutionalized and media-driven “taste makers,” and would promote the kind of critical knowledge that permits an enhanced range of informed musical choices.

Critical theory, in sum, seeks to recognize (i.e., re-cognize or re-think) human subjectivity and individuality as both a means and as an end of becoming fully human, fully rational. This means that if knowledge is to be valid, it must take into account subjective, contextual, situational factors. Humans are ‘subjectivities’ with goals, needs and intentions, not simply ‘objects’ controlled by natural laws. They have reason and therefore can formulate and evaluate personal and collective purposes, goals, and values (i.e., they have intentionality). They are agents who, alone and in communication with others, can act in their own behalf or on behalf of others or society, for example, in teaching or any of the helping professions.

In the next section, then, teachers who succumb to an “it works for me” kind of subjective technicism are revealed as engaging in a form of “false consciousness” that is as pragmatically ineffective in serving the music needs of students as is the “what works” prescriptions and recipes of scientistic technicism. Either form of technicism amounts to what I describe as “methodolatry” — an almost religious or cult-like attachment to particular “techniques,” “methods” or “materials” of teaching that too often fall far short of the kind of effective pragmatic results that are the ethical basis of teaching as a professional praxis.

III Origins and Problems of Uncritical Subjectivity

Human variability

Considered as agents, humans are not interchangeable. Human meanings vary according to context, situatedness, needs, goals and intentions. Ignoring such individuating factors reduces people to theoretical abstractions that are unreal. Whatever its value as basic or pure research undertaken for its own sake, such theoretical knowledge is so abstract that no direct application of it to human affairs qualifies as praxis. To begin with, only actions that serve humans according to the ethical criterion Aristotle called phronesis properly qualify as praxis. And secondly, in being put to such human use, theoria becomes diluted, its abstract purity compromised and reduced by its engagement with situated values. The low-level knowledge that remains becomes instrumental knowledge — a form of what, since the time of Aristotle, has been called techne or “craft.” For example, compare the knowledge of the physics of electricity possessed by a theoretical physicist and an electrician; the knowledge of chemistry possessed by a theoretical chemist and a medical doctor; or the theoretical knowledge possessed by a music theorist and a performing artist. In all these instances, praxis is achieved only in possession of a distant echo of theoretical purity and abstraction.

The academic or merely theoretical quality of “pure” research is the “elsewhereness” (Shor 1992) that most teachers see in positivist research: it comes from “elsewhere” than the very places that can or need to use it. In education, it comes from the research labs in Ivory Towers, not from or even in terms of teachers on the job. Because of this “elsewhereness,” teachers regularly ignore such research. Perhaps they intuit its laboratory sterility and its claims to statistical laws as lacking obvious connection with the untidy contingencies they face in ‘real life’ on the job. In any case, they are unable to understand the technical language of such pure theory enough to even attempt to apply it to their situations for whatever it might be worth as instrumental knowledge.

Teacher subjectivity

Instead, “true knowledge” for most teachers — knowledge of what they tend to call “the real world” — is typically subjective: it amounts to what seems to be the case for their particular situation. On one hand, however, as far as the average teacher knows, the “real world” of teaching begins and ends with her classroom. On the other hand, she assumes (unfortunately, in error) that other teachers experience more or less the same “reality” — that schools and teaching are basically the same except for minor local differences, and that the “things” are similar for most teachers in other classrooms and in other schools. Thus the “elsewhereness” of positivist research is rejected in favor of a radically subjective “hereness and nowness” where particular teachers are typically ‘in touch’ with only their own teaching circumstances, their own ideas and their own personal and teaching paradigms. Each, thus, does his or her “own thing” and the modern school amounts in effect to “x” number of one-room schools under one roof. As a result, “school systems” (note the technicist claim) function as collections of individual ‘operatives’ who are assumed to be contributing uniformly to a collective ‘system’ when, in point of fact, this is not the case at all.

One “thing” tends, unfortunately, to be commonplace. Lacking any consensus concerning tangible and pragmatic outcomes (i.e., outcomes that are useful outside of school), teachers fail to be sufficiently critical of the instruction they give in terms of its results for students and society. Actual benefits, then, are inconsistent, haphazard, variable, and unpredictable. The majority of what is learned is merely “academic”; it is relevant only in terms valued by the demands of the particular classroom and teacher, and the general program requirements of the individual school or state-wide ‘system’. In other words, “academic” learning is so situated, so classroom-based, that it cannot or does not transfer to or advance out-of-school musical benefits for students now and after graduation.

The following examples from the US may or may not be applicable in the same way or degree for other countries, but they serve to illustrate how instruction that is “merely academic” can fall short of making a real or pragmatic difference in the lives of individual students and thus falls short of being professional praxis comparable to the other helping professions. Thus, even though students typically have classroom music instruction for 6 to 8 years, few gain any functional music skills, or any musical independence; for example, the average “graduates” of general music classes cannot read music effectively for personal purposes. Nor do they typically develop a disciplined “taste” for any kind of music as a direct result of schooling. The vast majority who have been in ensembles (perhaps only 15 % of the school population to begin with), lack the independent musicianship to be active performers and the few that have such competency — usually the section leaders — do not seem to have learned to value active performing enough to make time for it in their lives (in the way, for example, amateur athletes continue to use their “physical education”). They do not remain musically active after graduation as performers or listeners; and they otherwise fail to show themselves to be musically different or improved in any way that can be directly attributed to their ensemble participation -beyond, arguably, its strictly social benefits.

Similar and other ineffective or merely academic results can doubtlessly be pointed out for other countries. Such ineffective or merely academic results can be pointed out at length. Faced with such disconcerting examples, music teachers place blame on the students (viz., that students lack talent, intelligence, a work ethic, etc.), parents (they are too lenient, too uninvolved, and don’t make their children practice), society (it doesn’t value education and “good music”), television (it diverts them from studying and practicing), and other scapegoats such as interscholastic sports, after-school jobs and the like.

Technicist teaching

Now it is true that there are many individual and social impediments to public schooling. However, teachers are all too accustomed to blaming these forces and rarely look to their own instruction as the primary source of poor results. As seen by most teachers, then, poor learning is not a matter of the technology of traditional methods and techniques they use for instruction. They take for granted that this technology of traditional “tools” serving traditional and taken-for-granted ends has been passed on as a craft of teaching from one teacher to another. The common wisdom holds that such traditional methods have been “proven” successful by the “test of time.” Teachers tend, therefore, to teach as they were taught. This includes, especially, teaching as they were taught to teach in their student teaching internships and, in general, by the “culture” of teaching that uncritically passes on teaching paradigms as technicist methods. Methods thus become taken-for-granted recipes and prescriptions used without regard for results.

Because such teachers assume that the competent use of the “good methods” sanctified by tradition or a particular institutionalized advocacy group automatically guarantees “good results,” they tend to focus on an quest for such activities and ideas to use. In consequence, aside from keen attention to whether students are generally cooperative, teachers too often ignore the goodness of results in terms of students’ actual musical competence and attitudes. As long as there is no major misbehavior, then, results are uncritically assumed to be good or good enough. That a lesson was merely practicable — i.e., could be “delivered” as “instruction” — becomes the criterion of “it works,” not whether students have the pragmatic ability to do anything new or better as a result of such instruction. Thus “delivering” or providing “instruction” is uncritically assumed to amount to “teaching.”

With the confusion introduced by this verbal self-deception, one’s “teaching” is effectively disassociated altogether from the criterion of whether one’s students are able to demonstrate valuable “learning.” The “process” called “teaching” becomes uncritically equated with the “product” called “learning.” As a result, “teaching” becomes nothing more than a certain generic process a person labeled (i.e., certified) a “teacher” undertakes, not an action or professional praxis qualified in terms of the results brought about for students. The very nature of a profession, particularly “helping professions” such as medicine, law, therapy, dentistry, nursing, teaching, and the like, is to bring about predictable and tangible benefits for the individual clients served. In this sense, a physician whose patients regularly remain sick or get sicker is a “doctor” in name, not in fact. And, applying the example to schooling, when instruction results in “clients” who remain “sick” or get “sicker” — that is, where there is no predictable or valuable learning on the part of students –“teaching” is equally a misnomer. What is called by that name is a certain going through the motions, not a praxis that is defined in terms of the results brought about.

Rationalization of music and teaching

That this conflating of “instructing” with “teaching” exists at all is another unfortunate consequence of modernism run amok. Before the modern development of what sociologists misleadingly call “the professionalization of teaching,” a “teacher” was any person from whom a student learned. The student was, in every sense of the word, a “disciple” of both the teacher and the teaching, and the idea of the scholarly “disciplines” still conveys the sense of being a life-long student of a field of inquiry. However, with the Enlightenment’s dictate for rationalism, all knowledge — along with virtually every aspect of society — was subjected to rationalization. It was thus analyzed, dissected, labeled with technical terms, theorized and codified into “disciplines” and collected in books such as the crown glory of the Enlightenment thinking, the first Encyclopedia. The aestheticizing of music by aesthetic theory is a key and relevant case at point.

A related type of rationalization or relevance to music educators in the Euro-American tradition is the invention and subsequent development of the “theory of music” as a “discipline.” This was also initiated during the Enlightenment, mainly by Rameau, one of the “Encyclopedists” — theorists and philosophers involved in compiling the first Encyclopedia in 1751. This “theory of music” rationalized the “common practice” of its time, yet is still taught today as “fact” in ‘theory’ and ‘harmony’ classes in high schools and universities despite its general irrelevance to contemporary musics of just about any kind or genre –with the possible exception, ironically, of very simple rock and pop musics. In fact, “music” can no longer be accounted for in terms of any traditional, all-embracing, universal or essentialist theory. Rather, with the postmodern explosion in the late 20th century of a pluralism of “musics,” there is no longer any semblance of “common practice.” In any case, “common practice” was at best a misnomer describing a certain rarefied and ‘uncommon’ taste for European Art music during a limited period in history. Thus despite the attempt to define “music” as a singular “thing” or process, or similar attempts to define an aesthetic essence for all music, such singular, universal or essentialist definitions of “music” simply no longer obtain when the pluralism of postmodern musics is properly recognized. These musics, each a separate praxis with its own unique characteristic qualities and criteria of musicianship and artistry, thus give lie to the pretense that any aesthetic theory of musical essentialism can rationalize either the value of such musics or can serve to guide them in praxis.

Teaching has also experienced a similar process of rationalization and systematization — the earlier mentioned “professionalization of teaching.” Beginning once again in the Enlightenment with such thinkers as the philosopher and Enclyclopedist Jean Jacques Rousseau, treatises and theories were issued in increasing number. And especially in the last century, empirical findings and theoretical conclusions from a variety of scholarly disciplines have been applied to educational theorizing. In addition, “schooling” itself became rationalized — formalized, systematized, and institutionalized — as “education,” such forces themselves being a direct consequence of the modernist paradigm that arises from the standardizing rationalism spawned by the Enlightenment. “Teaching” thus became a job description or an employment category in the field or business of “education” more than it described a successful praxis that resulted in a valuable product. And with the “training” of teachers in university departments of education we see this most important human activity itself subjected to a process of rationalization, systematization, standardization (i.e., graduation and certification ‘requirements’) and (supposedly) efficient assembly-line production techniques. This so-called professionalization resulted in the “certification” or official labeling of a standard operative called a “teacher” — a status that is too often quite irrespective of the individual’s ability to produce positive and functional results for students. The term professionalization was thus adopted early on by sociologists solely in consideration of the rationalization of teacher-training and the subsequent certification or licensing of teachers. As a result, it should not be confused with the need to reconstrue teaching as a professional praxis along the ethical and other pragmatic criteria typically advanced for the other major professions.

To be a “teacher,” in the modernist view, is to be “certified” to engage in a subjectively determined and fixed, technicist process called “teaching” that focuses on the competent use of “good (i.e., ‘standard’ or ‘traditional’) methods.” Evaluation of students (for example, “grades” — another invention that results from the quantifying and systematizing practices of modernist rationalism) uncritically assumes “teaching” with “good methods” and leads to the conclusion, “Well, I taught it to them; if they didn’t learn it, it is their fault!” Thus the methods and materials are taken for granted as “good” and, as shall be explained more below, the curriculum is equated with the simple use of those methods and materials (a situation comparable to turning on and going through the motions of using a vacuum cleaner without determining if the rug is actually being cleaned). Unfortunately neither the methods nor the curriculum are ever evaluated in terms of the goodness of actual results for students or society. The paucity of these results for “education” in general are increasingly commented on and criticized by everyone from politicians to taxpayers.

Music educators not only share in this criticism; some, particularly in secondary schools and higher education, are further criticized for their preference for working only with the elite, ‘talented’ few — a situation somewhat akin to a doctor who prefers only healthy patients! Whatever the paucity of results may be in terms of students’ mastery of cognitive and psychomotor skills, then, most music teachers, as is the case with their colleagues in other disciplines, seem to believe that such poor results are good or good enough under the circumstances. They accept that whatever results they manage to produce are rationally all that can be expected and, therefore, that such results are the ‘reasonable’ by-products of the competent use of good methods. However, as we have seen, when certain taken-for-granted methods are used to produce taken-for-granted (i.e., not critically analyzed) ends, a technology of teaching comes into being. The result is an almost religious belief in and thus a search for particular methods, “activities” and materials that are believed “to work.” “Good teaching,” in this uncritical, technicist view, is judged solely in terms of the efficient use of “good methods” and “good materials.”

“Methodolatry”

Such methods can be characterized into two general types: institutionalized and individualized. Each of the former type involves a ‘standardized’ technicist ‘system’ of techniques and materials that is widely adopted and followed along what are assumed to be uniform lines. Each such ‘system’ of uniform methodological practices meets all the standard criteria of a social institution: taken for granted paradigms that generate equally taken for granted practices and values; legitimation procedures that advocate the institution’s existence when actual results fall short of claimed values; proselytizing machinery for attracting, then initiating new conscripts; a historicity of approved practices that are passed on as “good” and accepted unthinkingly by conscripts as received wisdom; and, of course, experts who function as ‘managers’ of the institutional knowledge base, guardians and defenders of the status quo, and gatekeepers for controlling admission. Institutionalized methods, for all their claims to technical or systematic uniformity and standards, are nonetheless highly idiosyncratic in practice and eclectic in key ways dictated by the varying contexts and situatedness of teaching and learning and music, and by musical and personal differences between teachers. But the collective belief in and common discourse about “the method” even more strongly commits adherents and converts to the shared technological view of teaching. The sheer number of “believers” or “disciples” thus leads to an almost religious faith in the method that can be dubbed “methodolatry.”

Individualized methods, on the other hand, are developed by particular teachers from components of systematic methods, the eclectic methods of other teachers, and their own trial and error. They tend to be so personal, so idiosyncratic, so eclectic, so governed by the here-and-now of their situatedness, that two such teachers have very little in common. Thus discourse between them is typically very unproductive. More unfortunately, once formulated, an individualized method typically becomes rationalized, systematized and standardized into a personal technology of “what works for me” that is assumed to be “good teaching.” Thus the teacher assumes that because his methods are good, the results must also be good and, as with institutionalized methods, the goodness of results gets overlooked.

With either type of method, curricular ends are taken for granted and are not critically analyzed or stated in unequivocal terms. The simple use of the method and its associated materials is equated with curriculum. Simply using or “teaching the method” (e.g., “I teach the _____method”) becomes “teaching the curriculum.” Thus the process is automatically assumed to be the product and the medium becomes the message. In other words, “teaching” this or that “activity” may produce a certain degree of collective musical “activity” on the part of students during class, but little or no degree of personal musical agency results for individual students outside of or after graduation from school. Now if carpenters thought in this way, they would claim that simply using their “tools” amounts to “building.” With no “blueprint” in mind, then, they could simply chisel, saw, hammer and screw things together and still consider themselves to be “builders” despite the fact that their efforts never build anything useful. Many music teachers, with comparable assumptions in mind, similarly employ what they subjectively consider to be their “good methods” or “good tools of teaching” without a clear curricular “blueprint” to guide either their instructional efforts or to serve as the basis for evaluating the success of such instruction and of students’ learning.

“Endullment” of students

In practice, then, results too often are not only not good in terms of empowering students musically for life. Negative results and other unintended side effects often worsen the situation: for example, poor attitudes toward the irrelevance of music class itself; or, in ensembles, the averaging effect of large numbers that masks the musical weaknesses of individuals. To once again use a comparison from the health professions, not only don’t many patients get well as a result of treatment, they get sicker! Thus, to refer again to an example given earlier for the US, instead of developing “musical literacy” (i.e., student graduates who can all read, write, perform and understand music better as a result of their musical schooling), students too often give every indication of having been “turned off” in music class to such matters. Instead of gaining an “aesthetic education” (and whatever that might be, and how it is to be observed as evidence of successful teaching and learning are, of course, not specified), the result is an anesthetic education. Thus students too regularly are “endulled” and often undertake a “performance strike” (Shor, 1992) — a work stoppage or suspension of effort — and resist or reject and thus “tune out” or ignore what is taught in terms of their own musical functioning outside of class. And in ensembles, they either ignore practicing their instruments (preferring to use the ensemble as a social club) or quit studying or even playing instruments altogether. Typically the results are of the sort that all but guarantees that students will have little to do in their lives with the kinds of music studied in school. In any case, the musical skills, understanding and appreciation of typical school graduates extends no further than the informal tastes “educated” by the mass media. Thus music education fails to promote the kind of musical independence that could serve students throughout life.

In section four, after a summary of the first three sections, an account of praxis as a basis for professionalizing music education is offered. The need for ongoing ideology critique is also advanced as an ethical condition of the “critical consciousness” of professional problem-solving and responsibility that needs to replace the “false consciousness” of ideology-induced technicist teaching. And, most centrally, the importance to praxis of a warranted and well-designed curriculum is argued.

IV Curriculum: Ideology versus a Phronesis of “Good Results”

From the perspective of Critical Theory, being a teaching professional involves analyzing the kind of scientistic positivism (seen in part one) in terms critical of a technology of teaching (seen in part two) that denies the subjective particulars of individuals teachers, individual students and the situatedness of all teaching and learning. But, as explained in part three, the teacher as a professional is also critical of the “it works for me” kind of hand-me-down traditionalism where the criterion of what “works” has been defined more in terms of students who appear to be cooperative, having fun, etc., than in terms of pragmatic outcomes that empower them to be the agents of their personal musical lives. Whether inspired by scientism or traditionalism, that a method is practicable only means that it can be put into practice (i.e., has a history of past practice), not that it is pragmatic in terms of the beneficial results it brings about. Thus Critical Theory points to the need for teachers to be professionals engaged in praxis. This necessitates attending first and foremost to the goodness of results brought about for “clients” — i.e., the students.

Professional praxis

Professions, properly understood then, are not just specialized or skilled types of employment. A profession is a praxis and, in distinction to just any ‘practice’ or ‘doing’, a praxis is characterized and guided by a condition Aristotle called phronesis. This is the ethical criterion for “good results” that guides a professional practitioner to a primary concern with the pragmatic benefits experienced by the typical client. In the case of music education, individual students in music classes and ensembles are the clients served (i.e., not the class or ensemble as a collectivity). “Good praxis” (i.e., good teaching practice) in this “critical” view, can be judged only in terms of such a phronesis of “good results” for students. And “good results” are seen in terms of the degree to which, in the case of music teaching, individual students have been enabled as a result of their musical schooling to want to and to be able to engage themselves in musical praxis in ways and to a degree they find rewarding and empowering in life outside of and after graduation from school.

Teaching as a professional praxis (i.e., teaching as praxis, or “teaching praxis” for short) is thus distinguished from technicist teaching, the kind of craft-based technology that Aristotle called techne: prescriptive, traditional, instrumental knowledge employed in pursuit of taken-for-granted ends. Critical Theory is critical, then, of the kind of teacher subjectivity that ignores ethical praxis — practical and “good” human results for clients — by concerning itself, instead, with unwarranted reliance on methods of instruction used as a technology in pursuit of unquestioned, intangible goals (e.g., claims made for aesthetic education), atomistic taxonomies (e.g., the current advocacy by MENC in the United States of “teaching to the national standards”), or ideologically determined values.

Ideological consciousness

An ideology, as seen by Critical Theory, is a system of seemingly rational ideas, practices and paradigms that serve to justify or legitimate the values, vested interests, and beliefs of a particular group of people. Such groups either operate as a “ruling class” or “dominant culture,” or are engaged in some kind of “politics of recognition.” In either case, the group seeks to advance its socially created realities and interests against those of other groups. In sum, an ideology advances a group’s interests as being in the best interests of everyone else — even if the others who are supposedly to benefit from the ideology do not wish to have such beneficence forced upon them.

Public schooling is beset by multiple and competing political, economic, social and intellectual ideologies that function as external pressures and impediments to teaching praxis. Some ideologies, however, arise from within education generally and others from within each teaching specialty, such as the music education “establishment.” Individual teachers tend to be unaware of such ideological inconsistency and interference. And they uncritically “buy into” or allow them themselves to be “owned by” a particular ideological view or claim — in music education, for example, the vested interests of the publishing industry to sell music regardless of its quality, or the negative short and long term effects of the competitions and once-a-year festivals sponsored by state teacher organizations. Thus such unsuspecting teachers invariably encounter or create for themselves an often bewildering array of ideology-based obstacles to successful praxis.

Nonetheless, many teachers remain comfortable with their pat and pet assumptions and prefer to be ignorant of and thus untroubled by criticisms and alternatives. They are unwilling, then, to undertake the kind of personal and professional ideology critique that can identify dysfunctional paradigms, taken for granted assumptions, biases and unwarranted personal theories, and other such impediments to bringing about praxial results for typical students. Instead, too many become complacent followers of the status quo, or of every fad or bandwagon. Aside from their discomfort with the inevitable behavioral crises brought on by students who are “endulled” by the irrelevance of such teaching, they derive a certain solace from the predictability of their routines and continue in the same patterns — despite the fact that actual results often contradict the values or “goods” claimed by their curricular assumptions. An example of such a crisis would be the situation in music education where students are “turned off” to music by the very people who are trying to get them to “turn on” to the benefits schooling can make possible beyond what they entered the classroom knowing and valuing. Slogans and promotional campaigns by various music education organizations thus become necessary when music teaching fails to bring about the tangible and beneficial results that would be proof-positive of its value as a part of general education and its value for a life lived more fully as a result of musical schooling. Such advocacy would simply not be needed — in the current forms or degree, at least — if results promised by curricular claims of value were in fact the “goods” delivered.

Legitimation crises and ideology critique

Habermas, the leading Critical Theorist of our day, has analyzed this kind of mismatch between theory and practice — between ideological claims and results. When a system operates according to ideologies and practices that undermine its own raison d’etre, it experiences a state of perpetual crisis brought on by tensions resulting from the mismatch of values claimed for the system and values actually produced by the system. The result is a ‘loss of faith’ on the part of those who are supposed to be the beneficiaries of the ideology and its delivery system. Habermas calls these institutionally self-created contradictions, legitimation crises. They arise from the intractable problems and unintended negative results brought on by inherent contradictions and inconsistencies within the dominant ideology guiding the system and its ‘standards’. These internal contradictions and conflicts make the benefits that are only abstractly claimed in theory progressively more difficult to justify, rationalize or legitimize as being “good.” Thus, in the terminology of sociology, such ‘built-in’ crises bring about the need to legitimate the rationality and values of the system.

In schools and universities, for example, the hegemony of “classical music” that has resulted from the aesthetic ideology concerning music and musical value is widely under attack by postmodern multiculturalism for its ethnocentric bias. The result has been a legitimation crisis regarding the need for a definition of “music” and musical value that is more comprehensive and pragmatic than the aesthetic standards and values claimed for the Eurocentric canon of Art music and High Culture. The consequence has been pressures for a pluralistic inclusion of multicultural and world musics in schooling in order to support the claim that music is truly “basic” because it is truly relevant to the life well-lived.

Unfortunately, however, the resulting clamor for and thus rush to multicultural and world musics has, in turn, become a new ideological bandwagon. Including only token examples of such music fails to put “music” in its broadest and most representative praxial sense at the core of the curriculum and this minimizes the importance of just how “basic” such non- or un-aesthetic, “practical” musics are to life. Thus the only occasional use of these musics in public school, and the “token” and begrudging offering of a “world music” course in universities, pays only lip-service to a breadth and wealth of musics that should be a central part of all instruction that is properly called “music” education. Since broad sociocultural ideologies are at stake, music teachers are regularly subjected to the pressures of various social class interests concerning competing ideas of “classy” and “good” music, and to questions concerning which or whose music should be taught in schools, and why. Without ideology critique that can sort out such competing claims, unsuspecting teachers simply “go with the flow” and not surprisingly end up “swept away” in curricular directions that fall short of teaching as praxis.

The first stage of an ideology critique entails a process called immanent critique where the claims made by an ideology are used as the criteria by which the results of the ideology are evaluated. Music in schools of most industrialized nations is typically supported on the claim that it is “basic” in some way to the general education of all students. However, when the claims made by supporters of the aesthetic ideology for the benefits of aesthetic responsiveness are used as the criteria by which aesthetic-based music education is judged, it is clear that such values are not part of the general education of most school graduates whose musical tastes and habits remain virtually unaffected by such musical schooling. It is not even clear that graduates of school-based ensembles have received an “aesthetic education” since few remain musically active after graduation and since the listening tastes and habits of most have not been turned in more aesthetic directions. Immanent critique can similarly be used to sort out claims sometimes heard that multicultural and world musics in the curriculum somehow lead to better understanding and mutual respect between cultural groups. If in fact such music contributes only to a certain “politics of recognition” where each cultural group in a school has “its music” included in the total curriculum, students can be seen to “tune out” all but “their own” music or at most take a short-lived esoteric interest in certain musical differences from “their own” music. Results not infrequently lead to greater, not lesser musical and cultural insularity. Thus in cases like these, and others that will be characteristic of local situations (including university-level music education), where actual results contradict ideological claims, immanent critique helps teachers from being swept away by either traditions or fads that fall short of praxial results that make some tangible difference in the lives of students.

In addition to immanent critique, teachers must begin to use their own reason to identify praxial results that would empower students to become agents of their own musical destinies in life outside of and after graduation from school. There is always more to teach than there is time and resources to teach. Hence, the diagnoses made in and of a given situation that lead to a curriculum — or, properly speaking, the diagnoses that should lead to a written curriculum — involve decisions that are always philosophical since they rely on critical analyses of value. In music teaching, such curricular theorizing concerning musical value amounts to answering the question “What is music good for in life?” The resulting curricular problem of “What of all that can be taught is most worth teaching?” is a matter determining the most accessible pragmatic “goods'”(values) that music can provide for the greatest number of people.

Curriculum for musical praxis

A pragmatic answer to this over-riding curricular question rejects, first of all, metaphysical issues that cannot be adjudicated in concrete terms at all, or issues that do stand up well to the process of immanent critique. Thus it does not involve fine and noble platitudes and claims about the aesthetic benefits of music that cannot be evaluated in terms of teaching success or in terms of the benefits of the lives of individual students. To be successful, curriculum cannot succumb to the legitimation crises created by the use of aesthetic theory and its claims of “aesthetic disinterestedness,” “aesthetic distance,” and “for-its-own-sake” kinds of musical purity, while at the same time claiming that music education as aesthetic education is somehow basic in a pragmatic, useful sense to general education. Thus, a pragmatic curriculum — a curriculum for music as praxis — will not reflect the kinds of aesthetic claims that involve the increasingly problematic legitimation crisis concerning elitism versus populism — good taste versus popular tastes — and the resulting problem of students who are increasingly turned off to the kinds of “good music” that are alone are said to have appropriate aesthetic benefits.

Instead, a pragmatic curriculum will be guided by a phronesis of “personal action” with music. Music in this praxial sense is “for” personal praxis or agency — that is, for creating or experiencing “good time” in life through music. “Good time” is well spent — the expression “worthwhile” literally means “good time” — and thus musical agency is an important means by which humans make a life worth living. In other words, a curriculum for musical praxis is first and foremost concerned to insure that students want to and are able to avail themselves of a wider and altogether richer variety of musical choices for enriching their lives than would have been the case without formal schooling. For Critical Theory, then, the ethical criterion of successful, professional teaching praxis in music education — i.e., the phronesis of a curriculum predicated on authentic praxis — will be to empower students to improve the quality of their lives through music. “Good music” will be seen or evaluated according to the incredible breath of “good results” that music considered as praxis can bring to humans being and becoming human.

Such a praxial theory of music, then, is not exclusive; for example, in the way major aesthetic theories exclude as properly or fully aesthetic “popular” and other “useful” musical praxes such as Christmas songs, folk music, much-admired “non-classical” instruments such as the accordion and other indigenous instruments, music used in religious worship, music for dance, advertising, film and television dramas, political advocacy, and therapy, as well as a host of other everyday, down-to-earth, examples of how “basic” music really is in life. Instead, a praxial theory of music is inclusive of just such countless important ways in which music of all kinds and types serves humankind — including “concert music” of all kinds intended for “just listening.” Music as praxis serves not just solitary individuals who listen to music as a self-sufficient action, as is the case with the Art music tradition of Eurocentric concert music; instead, it encompasses all types of musical praxis that serve individual and social needs and uses — for example, music for weddings and other ceremonies and celebrations.

Furthermore, music as praxis includes and advances all kinds, degrees or skill levels of individual, recreational and amateur music-making, and all such genres of music involved in creating such “good time,” as valuable or “good” for the individuals directly served. It is therefore not restricted to just the “classy” music of any style or genre, or to performance standards of professional “artists” and other “experts.” A praxial view of music also properly recognizes that music carries an inescapable and important sociality. “Just listening” as an audience member, for instance, is not simply a matter of “listening alone” among others; it is inherently a social experience occasioned by music. Thus it includes the social communality of the audience as part of the “meaning” experienced in connection with the music. Even listening alone at home takes part in a social universe of meaning: aside from the fact such recorded and broadcast music presumes a “virtual” audience, the facticity of the music of the moment itself — the social process by which individuals regard it as a “thing” or a “work” — inherently presumes institutionally sanctioned and culturally created meaningfulness. This sociocultural component extends to the “meaning of music” itself which, in the praxial view, is thus not exclusively internal, intrinsic or for-its-own-sake as claimed by the dichotomizing categories of aesthetic theory. It is instead inclusive of an almost unimaginable variety of social and cultural meanings, intentions, influences and traits that importantly include the broader and ultimately situated influences of society and culture and the inherent sociality of sound and its use (or misuse).

“No man is an island,” it has famously been said. And, in the praxial view of music, the isolated or autonomous audience member is thus a fiction aesthetic theory has taken for granted as part of the larger European paradigm that stresses the isolated individual and correspondingly ignores or minimizes the social amplifiers and determinants of culture and the communal intentionality that conditions any lifeworld. Furthermore, the idea that a “work” of music is self-referential, for-its-own-sake, or otherwise an autonomous “expression” of the composer’s (or humankind’s) “inner life” that is isolated, cerebralized and reified as the absolute (and absolutely Good) formal or expressive meanings claimed to be “in” a score — this idea is equally unwarranted and oversimplified. The “feelings” accounted for by praxial theory are visceral, affective experiences far more direct, immediate, down-to-earth and basic than the typical high-minded claims made for the cerebralized, intellectualized and aestheticized “forms of feeling” or “pure forms” promised by leading aesthetic theories.

With a curriculum in mind that is rooted in the realities of ubiquitous musical praxis that is thus “basic” to the lives of typical people (i.e., not professionally trained musicians), the question “What is good music?” is answered only in terms of how well this or that music serves the particular “goods” (values) identified in the curriculum as advancing “good time” and thus the “good life” through music. “Good pedagogy” (i.e., successful teaching), then, becomes a matter of how well the methods and materials serve the particular “goods” included in the formal curriculum. Thus goodness of results determines the goodness of the teaching. The curriculum itself, in turn, will be judged as “good” to the degree that its hypotheses of value — what music is good for in life — actually prove over time to be good “in action” for typical students throughout life.

Critical consciousness

Starting with the ubiquity of music as basic to the good life, then, the formal school curriculum for music as praxis seeks to enhance and advance the musical skills, attitudes and choices of students beyond what would otherwise be the case without such schooling. In order to create the conditions for such successful teaching praxis, then, critical teachers need to use their reason to identify social, political, economic, and other ideological forces that influence them and their schools in directions opposed to the desirable curricular results needed if students are to be empowered to be effective agents of their own musical destinies. By identifying such contrary or detrimental influences, individual teachers are thus empowered to become more effective agents of their own calling as teachers. Being aware of impediments to their success, critical teachers prepare themselves to solve problems that, for other less aware teachers, directly exert significant negative impact that typically goes unaddressed. For example, being critically alert to the negative potential of the various social, economic, political and intellectual forces seeking to dominate public schooling, a critically conscious teacher is better prepared to minimize and otherwise cope more successfully with the negative impact these forces will invariably have in each and every classroom. Critical music educators, then, will seek to understand teaching praxis in terms of local, regional and national conditions that can divert instruction and impede the curriculum.

But, as has already been pointed out, beyond such broad-based external ideological impositions, various forces and paradigms within the field of music education itself also have important ideological overtones that can exert equally detrimental influence on curriculum and instruction. These need to be critically evaluated as well if legitimation crises and other negative effects are to be avoided or minimized. As we have already seen in earlier contexts, these ideological forces involve the narrow-minded and uncritical acceptance of ideas, theories, practices, values and the like that have great bearing on teaching praxis. Rather than consider alternatives, these traditions are received as matters of fact, and thus are not subjected to immanent or ideology critique, despite the negative potential for the technicist harm pointed out earlier. Evidence of these kinds of potentially detrimental influences are seen at all levels of music education.

Take, once again, the example of a “what works” technological or technicist approach to teaching that was analyzed earlier in relation to scientistic positivism. In this new context, we see it as an ideology that, in essence, claims that certain “good” methods or materials can be identified by empirical research or the ‘field trials’ and ‘traditions’ of practitioners as being invariably successful — as “working” — and thus as technologically “good for” all students and society. While this is not the place to argue the issue in depth, it should be obvious that, just as the successful use of tools by a carpenter is seen only in how well built and how useful the results are, any criterion of “what works” in teaching needs to take into consideration curricular results. And since, as we have seen, curriculum is a matter of answering the question, “What of all that can be taught is most worth teaching?, it is, in essence, a matter of values that require philosophical clarification and determination. In short, “what works” simply cannot be a value free, scientific, technological issue claimed by advocates. Rather, the criterion of “what works” needs to be evaluated according to the criterion of phronesis — that is, “what works” is strictly a matter of getting “good results” for students.

Praxis is not reducible to algorithmic “what works” kinds of formulaic “techniques.” All questions of praxis — in any profession or field of action — are determined in terms of the “presenting” context of each particular situation. In medicine, for example, diagnoses are made in terms of the “presenting” patient — the medical symptoms and other evidence shown by this patient, on this occasion — and prescriptions are not routine, automatic and interchangeable. Similarly, teaching methods and materials can not be routine, automatic and interchangeable “prescriptions” for the same reason that even in medical practice not all prescriptions “work” well for all patients or at all for some patients. Instead, the methods and materials a teacher uses are only “tools.” They need to be properly chosen and used appropriately in terms of the criteria for action provided by the builder’s “blueprint” — in our case, the curriculum.

For example, the MENC organization in the United States unwittingly supports and advances a technicist view through many of its activities, publications and advocacy functions. One current example is the all-out effort to improve music teacher accountability by promoting certain “recommended activities” for teaching this or that item on its extensive list of institutionally created and approved “national standards.” In other countries, the imposition by ministries of education and other agencies of a variety of politically motivated programs, standards and examinations has had similar technicist consequences. To begin with, from the point of view of teachers in-the-trenches at least, these standards are just one more unwelcome instance of “elsewhereness.” And from the perspective of Critical Theory, this kind of hierarchy of codified, rationalized, systematized, standardized ‘quality control’ is but one more manifestation of the technicist rationality already criticized in several earlier contexts. But, in any case, despite the best of intentions, such imposition of standards from on high are usually so extensive, fragmented, technical and abstract that no teacher could ever possibly put Humpty Dumpty together in a holistic way that creates a fully functional, musical individual.

Music teacher organizations are also culpable, for example when they advance the “what works” mentality at their conferences. These become opportunities for certain favored or self-proclaimed teaching experts to demonstrate “if it works for me it will work for you” kinds of methods and materials for other teachers in need of a quick technological “shot in the arm” — i.e., prescriptions — rather than opportunities for critical colloquy and professional analysis. Various institutionalized groups committed to the advancement of this or that “method” are, of course, also primary examples of the technicist approach to “what works.” The resulting “methodolatry” is a prime example of the mistaken assumption that a method and its associated materials are, de facto, a successful and pragmatic curriculum. “Methods” and “techniques” courses in universities based on these and other prescriptive “methods” are often particularly guilty of advancing the idea that teaching is simply a technology of techniques that once ‘perfected’ by practice (particularly during “practice teaching, ” as it used to be called) simply “work” for all times and in all places. This approach to “teacher training” fails to predicate teaching methods on appropriate prior considerations of the types of curricular outcomes such teaching “tools” are supposed to serve — i.e., the formal curricular outcomes that should serve as the criteria for evaluating the success or “goodness” of methods and materials. Hence, it is altogether rare for pre-service music education students to receive any instruction whatsoever in matters of curriculum, in large part because music education “professors” are often woefully uninformed about curriculum writing and theory or have a vested professional interest in advancing only a particular method to the exclusion of all other possibilities. And in any case, the literature available in music education on curriculum theory is in fact negligible — a condition that could be either the cause for or result of the lack of such background on the part of teachers of methods and materials courses.

The lack of any foundational background in curriculum is thus a major impediment to the “student” teacher. Finally given the chance to put theory-taught-as-technological-fact into “practice” (but, unfortunately, not into praxis since the ethical imperative of praxis requires pragmatic benefits for students), the student teaching “internship” all but guarantees that neophyte teachers will be socially inducted into the “what works” mentality. At the very least they are sensible enough to figure out that “success” (i.e., “survival”) and good letters of recommendation result only from adopting many of the techniques used by the cooperating teacher (who, in turn, was similarly influenced years ago). Of course, most beginning teachers quickly discover that the conditions and circumstances of their first jobs are different and that what “worked” in student teaching (or when they were students) doesn’t necessarily succeed at all or in the same way in another situation — in fact, relocated “master” teachers often experience similar problems. In this regard, it is useful to keep in mind once more that the criterion of “what works” is all too often narrowly defined as not much more than “smoothly running classes of cooperative students” rather than in terms of “individual students musically empowered” to a newly enriched musical possibilities “for life.” In any event, exactly how the cooperating teacher over time “engineered” or “mastered” the situation to facilitate his or her methods is not something the student teacher can ever observe. Furthermore, since few “what works” teachers can analyze their successes, their mentoring of interns and beginning teachers is ineffective in promoting a thoughtful and reflective approach to teaching praxis.

One important “lesson” many student teachers learn, then, is the need to adjust the first teaching situation to the “system” or “method” of “activities” they mastered during their internships — rather than, that is, adjusting the method to the situational requirements of praxis. Newly graduated music teachers often have other precedents for single-minded teaching methods since it is all too typical that in their own music lessons in the university of conservatory they were expected to adjust to the pedagogy of their teachers. Few studio teachers have developed a range of pedagogical approaches that meet the needs of students and a single-minded, “what works” approach to musical instruction is unfortunately a paradigm that is difficult for new teachers to resist.

As a result, music teachers typically begin their careers with this model of adapting students and the teaching situation to the needs of the teacher and his or her preferred technology of methods rather than determining the methods that best suit curricular needs. Moreover, curriculum is tacitly based on the technological model of student teaching. Thus, the average music teacher begins a career without a formal (i.e., written) curriculum of his or her own or without any intention of evaluating the de facto curriculum that is instead the haphazard result of the instructional model provided by the student teaching internship. Instead, because the first teaching position demands more or other than what sufficed during student teaching, the beginning teacher is focused from the first on finding, using and “practicing” various “canned” or “teacher-proof” lessons and “activities,” numerous “bags of tricks,” and other technicist prescriptions — many suggested by well-meaning older teachers themselves in the uncritical grasp of technicist assumptions.

As in student teaching, “success” will be judged against the ‘norm’ of cooperative students and smoothly running classes, not in terms of actual musical benefits for the long run in the lives of individual students. Student teaching as presently institutionalized contributes to this less than satisfactory result by its almost single-minded concern with individual lessons or rehearsals and its corresponding lack of concern with demonstrations of long-term learning. Student teachers at best “plug in” to the cooperating teacher’s de facto curriculum. Even if a formal curriculum can be produced for the student teacher who dares to ask to see it, the student quickly notes that it is either not followed at all, or is not “delivered” as designed and thus plays no role in the evaluation of students or of teaching success. Thus instruction by student teachers is rarely evaluated in terms of where or how well the formal curriculum is actually “covered,” and even more rarely evaluated in terms of whether claims as to the value of proposed curricular outcomes are verified as being truly “good for” empowering students to get into action musically in ways that can be attributed directly to their musical schooling. Furthermore, because college supervisors see only random samples of lessons, evaluation of student teaching is focused almost exclusively on isolated instances of teaching, not on overall results.

All of these problems with and negative instances of ideological influences point to the need for individual teachers to engage in ideology critique at both the personal and professional levels. They simply need to identify, analyze and assess personal ideological suppositions, inherited paradigms and other tacit and taken-for-granted assumptions. In fact, from the point of view of becoming a critical teacher, this process ought to begin early in the teacher preparation process and should continue in formal ways throughout student teaching. This way the habits of critical consciousness that need to be applied to one’s own teaching are properly nurtured (see Rose, 1994 for a good example in music education).

Communicative competence and collaborative action

However, the collective nature of schools and schooling eventually requires any teacher to cope successfully with other teachers. Thus, open, reasoned and uncoerced communication among teachers in a school — at the very least the music teachers — and between other teachers in the field of music is needed.

This process of what Habermas calls communicative action must also begin in music education courses. Here, under proper guidance, students should be both exposed to and learn to deal cooperatively and collaboratively with a wide variety of different views and opinions. Thus the essentially philosophical undertaking of developing a warranted point of view based on evidence, competence with basic philosophical knowledge and processes, and clear thinking and writing, should begin in a context of diverse and plural opinions and beliefs not dissimilar from what will be experienced on the job. It should not foreclose or narrow the philosophical and practical options of neophyte teacher, for example by submitting them to a particular technology of teaching. Rather than focusing solely on single-minded and simplistic technical matters and the professor’s pedagogical preferences, “critical instruction” should help expand an awareness of and sophistication in dealing with and expressing philosophically difficult matters of value and questions of praxis.

Such philosophical and communicative competence should be devoted to encouraging productive dialogue on curricular matters. When some reasonable degree of consensus can be reached on such matters, it can be expected, even desired, that — on the job — different teachers will be able to reach common goals by different means. In other words, just as any two lawyers will approach a court case differently yet reach the same result for their clients, so teaching as professional praxis involves both an individual approach to reaching desirable outcomes and the personal and professional rewards associated with such individual achievement. The special problem for teaching as a profession, however, is the lack of easily agreed to or obviously “good” outcomes. In law it is perfectly obvious that winning the case is good, and in surgery that the patient should be relieved of pain and suffering. While there are other ethical dimensions to such professions (for example, questions of “malpractice”), the basic phronesis by which “goods” are observed is usually quite clear.

To attain a similar status for judging the success of this or that teaching technique, curricular results in music education need to be stated in terms of regulative or action ideals. All professions are guided by such ideals — for example, in the case of medicine, to restore health, to minimize or alleviate pain and, above all, to do no harm. Such ideals are not “idealistic.” Even though no perfect or “ideal” state of human affairs can ever be reached, they can be imagined. Thus regulative or action ideals are optimum states towards which people naturally strive or by which they judge the relative success of their actions. Action ideals thus guide or regulate action (i.e., praxis) by guiding it in certain directions that, being posited as ideal, are understood from the first as being incapable of final instantiation or perfect solution. For example, “love” or any one of the Ten Commandments is an action ideal, as is a musical score, or the physician’s ideal of extending life. A curriculum, then, is an articulated and functional arrangement of such action ideals for guiding teaching praxis in the same way a score guides certain kinds of musical praxis.

A written (formal) curriculum for music thus involves hypothesizing action ideals that analyze and represent desirable, optimum states of musical functioning. It describes in holistic terms the “good results” ethically expected from a teacher’s praxis (or from each individual among a group of teachers following an agreed upon curriculum) and from the curriculum itself. To be praxial, such holistic results must be “authentic” and thus capable of being put into action both in the classroom and “in life.” A delivered curriculum (curriculum as “instructed”) can never fully satisfy or reach these optimum states. But, in teaching as praxis, the effective curriculum amounts to the actual results in terms of musically praxial benefits for individual students.

In this ‘critical’ view, then, the process of “instruction” based on “delivering” a formal curriculum is necessarily distinguished from “teaching” as a praxis that results in an effective curriculum. In the first place, a formal curriculum will be incapable of supporting effective curricular results if improperly conceived or written. And, in the case of where appropriate formal curriculum is used to organize and guide instruction, “teaching” is seen only when such “instruction” (i.e., methods, materials, evaluation, etc.) is effective in terms qualified by the curriculum. “Teaching,” thus redefined pragmatically and ‘critically’, is always benefited by being drawn and inspired in the direction of such optimum results, and is judged and changed over time by using such action ideals as criteria for improvement.

Any consideration concerning action ideals for curriculum, in sum, is a philosophical undertaking. When it includes a group of teachers planning curriculum together, it also requires ‘critical argumentation’: the ability first to ‘critique’ an issue, contention, assumption or “problem” in terms acceptable to all, then to argue (in the best professional sense) and communicate successfully the fruits of that critique in the direction of increased empowerment of all concerned. “Teaching,” then, is not the simple use of a technology or tools of instruction; rather, it is the praxis of realizing effective results for students for life. The “standards” of effectiveness for teaching praxis are indicated by the action ideals of a formal curriculum conceived in terms of empowering students to music as a praxis. Such standards for praxis become “common standards” when they are conceived collectively by all those in a community charged with “instructing” students. However, there will be no “standard practice” or technology for reaching the common criteria of the formal curriculum. Thus teaching as praxis is at once an individual and individualizing undertaking. “Teachers,” thus, derive the kind of personal benefits and pleasures from professional praxis that are denied technicists whose efforts and results are at best more like the repeatable, routine, impersonal efforts of factory workers.

In the next section, teaching as professional praxis is seen to draw upon empirical research in generative, rather than prescriptive ways, particularly in the form of action research. The praxial knowledge guiding teaching, then, is not a matter of mere trial and error. It is shown to be a highly reflective process that results in large part from treating teaching as a type of action research.

V Critical Theory, Research Theory and Teaching As and For Praxis

With effective ongoing communication among teachers functioning as professionals, agreement as to what should constitute an effective curriculum is progressively realized — total or perfect agreement being rare. Critical Theory then points to the need for individual and collective action plans of change agency by which such curricular agreement can be translated into the kind of teaching praxis that enhances the role of music as praxis in the lives of students. At the very least, such action plans for change and improvement need to be characterized by some degree or type of action research. Such research is not done in order to make generalizations about learning that can be used as a technology with all learners in all times and places. It is first and foremost undertaken by individuals (or cooperative groups) to improve personal (or local) teaching praxis. Any generalization of results is not considered to be law-like; it holds only for that teacher or group, in that situation, for the near future.

Reflective teaching

Action research can span a range from formal to informal. Critically reflective teaching typically proceeds in the spirit of informal action research. Such teaching involves two levels of hypotheses that are “tested” in action: first, each ‘lesson plan’ is considered to be a hypothesis. Thus the methods and material hypothesized as being “good” for advancing a curricular goal are evaluated in terms of how well observable results meet such curricular criteria. Secondly, over time, the “goodness” of the curriculum itself — the goodness claimed by its theory of particular values — is treated as a theory that needs to be reflected on in terms of the evidence of long-term benefits for students.

This kind of “diagnose-hypothesize-test-observe-reflect” process, carried on in an unending spiral called “teaching” is a rational and empirical approach to teaching that is scientific in spirit without being scientistic or technicist in its claims or procedures. More thorough and systematic formal action research will typically be reserved for major decisions by an individual or group that involve general or overall questions of methods and relevant resources — such as whether curricular ideals for music reading in the elementary levels are served better by systematic instruction on classroom melodic instruments or by the more traditional singing approach. The traditional approach necessarily copes with problems of vocal pitch matching, in addition to decisions concerning whether solfege or number systems will be used and, if so, which ones. On the other hand, while students in choruses who ‘read’ at all or best are most likely those who play melodic instruments, large group instruction on classroom instruments poses its own options concerning the choice of instruments and teaching materials. The issue could be decided through formal action research rather than according to arbitrary and untested technicist claims. Only such an approach can accommodate local differences of resources, scheduling, staffing, and student profiles and needs.

Results of both formal and informal action research also need to be communicated among other practitioners (locally and beyond) with a view to the possibility that the knowledge conditions of a certain practice (i.e., its “theory”) can be adapted and thus ‘practiced’ by others along similar lines. Just as the praxis of one surgeon can be ‘adapted’ and ‘practiced’ by other surgeons, so the praxis of a teacher always has potential for being shared. Thus some teaching theories or models can become something akin to common praxis for reaching certain shared curricular results — that is, common standards — without the expectation of a standard practice or technicist method that is the same for everyone. Such common standards are comparable to “standards of care” in medicine and, as in medicine, there will be no standard practice that can or needs to be qualified in terms of long, detailed lists of “standards,” national or otherwise. In teaching as and for praxis, then, there can be no universal technology of teaching, no slavish “teaching the standards,” no “what works,” no uncritical adherence to ideological influences of any kind. “Good results” will be a matter of individual praxis — a praxis nonetheless informed by a community of practitioners (local and beyond) unified more by their commitment to a common standard or phronesis to get students “into action” musically than by uniform or standard teaching techniques.

Teachers also need the opportunity and the ability, therefore, to be able to analyze the action research and successful teaching practices of others critically in terms of the needs and other conditions of their own instructional situations and practices. For example, instead of “show and tell” demonstrations of discrete techniques and sample “activities” at teacher conferences, presentations would deal with descriptions and analyses of the action research process that has led to the adoption of a particular teaching praxis. Rather than presenting the praxis as a prescription or recipe, the empirical data and theoretical premises of the praxis in question would be shared and discussed in a way that would allow other teachers to formulate ‘experiments’ that are suited to their own teaching circumstances.

Such attempts to share praxis (in distinction to sharing technicist methods) would profitably adopt something of the format of scientific research. First would be a statement of “the problem.” This would amount to an account of the formal curricular action ideals at stake and the relevant philosophical warrants supporting their “goodness” — i.e., why and how the curricular goals in question are “good.” This account would allow audience members to assess the relevance or goodness of such curricular ideals in critical terms for their own praxis. Second, following this statement of the “curriculum problem” would be a review of the relevant theoretical and research “literature” that warrants the praxial application in question — i.e., the hypothesis at stake concerning whether the methods and materials are “good for” the curricular ideals at stake. It is important to note that praxial knowledge of various kinds are at stake in any such praxis, not a discrete practice presented as a method, technique, recipe or prescription. Thus this background of relevant literature would allow fellow teachers to adapt or ‘practice’ for themselves the practical knowledge in question — the knowledge resulting from the presenting teacher’s action research — to the situatedness of their own teaching rather than uncritically adopt it as a “what works” technology.

As a third step, the student population with whom the praxial knowledge in question was developed would also need to be carefully presented as being only a “selected sample,” not as “universally representative” of all students. On one hand, this allows audience members to make relevant comparisons and critical analyses with regard to their own student populations. On the other hand, it removes any possible implication that the praxial knowledge being shared is or can be a universal technique. And, finally, despite the success that warrants the sharing of such praxial knowledge in the first place, results should nonetheless be critically analyzed with a view to ongoing shortcomings that need to be improved. This would make it clear that the knowledge base for praxis being shared is not a “perfected” technique or a definitive “finding” of “what works,” but rather an ongoing hypothesis that, in the best scientific traditions, “needs more research” or refinement. In general, “methods” and “techniques” classes for teachers-in-training and in-service workshops also ought to follow these same four parameters. Teachers, in sum, need to be able to communicate their findings accurately to others if they are to create and contribute to a professional community of shared standards and a sharable fund of praxial knowledge — knowledge that results from successful praxis and that serves as a starting point for further praxis.

Putting theory into practice

In addition to such praxial knowledge, and despite the fact that Critical Theory has been critical of positivist claims that only science provides valid or valuable knowledge, teachers also need to be able to locate, understand and use “basic” research (i.e., theoria in Aristotle’s discourse). Teaching as action research simply needs to be firmly grounded in relevant and practicable empirical and theoretical research of various kinds — especially the kind of philosophical research that draws on warrants from diverse, relevant disciplines. In general, considerable theoria of this kind already exists that can be useful in guiding teaching in the same way that basic research theory supports but does not dictate the practice of medicine. When stripped of any positivist implications that such “findings” represent or point directly to a technology of “what works,” then empirical, historical, sociological and philosophical research can and should serve as part of the process by which action research for teaching is undertaken. Thus teachers should consult applicable research theory and empirical findings. And in their collegiate coursework and student teaching, neophyte teachers need be required to demonstrate this process successfully “in action.”

When theoretical and empirical research is applicable to teaching, it is generative not prescriptive. Such research combined with praxial knowledge generates hypotheses for likely courses of action — i.e., hypotheses that are comparable to a physician’s “diagnoses” — which always must be “tested in action” and evaluated by comparison to the ethical criteria of “good results” provided by curriculum. This process of first generating such hypotheses-diagnoses, then testing and evaluating them against action ideals indicated in the written curriculum, is the minimum condition of teaching as praxis — teaching as a profession! However, successful “tests” never become recipes. To begin with, it is not the “technique” or the “method” chosen that “works”; it is the praxial and theoretical knowledge that “works” in the hands of a suitably informed and reflective teacher to bring about musically praxial results.. And, in any case, no such successful instance is ever final or perfect; and praxial knowledge, by definition, is defined in terms of human values and needs that are forever variable. Thus the action research process is never-ending; it represents a perpetual quest for success that is never completed. Furthermore, teaching praxis also demands that the action ideals of the written curriculum also be treated as hypotheses; they too need to be adjudicated in terms of whether their claimed values (the “goodness” they propose) actually result in discernible benefits — i.e., whether or the degree to which musical values or “goods” result for students in “life.”

Finally, although musical competence is clearly a necessary and absolutely central condition of successful music teaching, it is not a sufficient condition. A more effective, functional balance between musical praxis and teaching praxis is needed in the preparation of teachers than is presently the case. Competent musical performers are fully mindful of and thus constantly reflect on the effectiveness of their practicing in terms of praxis — i.e., the goodness of results. Similarly, music teachers become mindful and reflective critical educators and thus professionals to the degree they become more competent in using basic research findings and curricular theory to improve their praxis.

It has been said that “nothing is so practical as a good theory.” Thus, despite the fact that, since Aristotle, theoria has been undertaken and contemplated for its own sake, theory of various kinds and levels of sophistication is also necessary to guide praxis. However, it is teachers who must adapt theory into praxial knowledge according to situated criteria — just as physicians must do according to the “symptoms” of the “presenting” patient and the other conditions of their medical practice (for example, surgeons on the battlefield “operate” under different conditions than they do in a modern medical center, yet must still get “good results”). Teachers cannot expect theoreticians and researchers to frame such research theory in universal, technicist terms, nor should they expect or accept the misleading “what works” claims of “applied research.” That, from the view of Critical Theory, falls into the scientistic assumptions and ideologies of positivism and of teaching as a “what works” technology. Technicist teaching amounts to renouncing the need and responsibility of each professional to “diagnose” and “treat” each situation according to the ethical criterion of phronesis that guides effective praxis in teaching, just as in medicine or any other professional praxis.

Praxial knowledge

For music teaching to be a profession, then, there needs to exist a reasonable, pragmatic consensus within a community of professionals concerning the nature of the ideal curricular results towards which teaching praxis in music education is devoted and by which it is evaluated. From the point of view of Critical Theory, such common standards should be pragmatic in all respects. Praxis, in this professional account then, involves an ethical commitment to getting the “right results” — meaning, in our case, musical and personal results that empower student-clients to be musical agents of their present and future musical fortunes. Furthermore, music teachers are professional to the degree that through “practice” they develop a personal “feel” for practical judgment (diagnosing and hypothesizing) and decision-making, rather than proceeding uncritically according to received technical traditions. Thus, critical educators function as intellectual models and philosophical leaders within a community of similarly committed professionals, not as unmindful technicians or uncritical followers. They are fully aware of changing research and theory on a broad professional scale, and continually change and improve their practice accordingly. And because they learn in and from the results of their own teaching actions judged in terms of students’ progress, they are their own best knowledge base.

The kind of “learning by doing” that results from the application of theory in terms of practical judgments based on ethics of praxis is referred to as praxial knowledge. Praxis generates personal knowledge on the part of the practitioner. This is why Aristotle considered praxis to be a form of knowledge and not simply any unreflective ‘practice’ or ‘doing.’ Habermas, building on this traditional view of praxial knowledge, has advanced a contemporary theory of praxial knowledge that has been applied by others to teaching as a praxis (viz., Carr and Kemmis, 1986). One component of such knowledge is the realization that no praxis ever attains “final” or “perfected” methods and techniques. Instead, teachers must always be critically alert to their own fallibility. They judge their success as teacher-professionals only in terms of tangible “goods” that clearly benefit students in ways and to a degree that would not have been possible without formal instruction in schools or studios. Medicine as a profession learns (generates praxial knowledge) from its mistakes and failings when patients die or get worse. Teaching requires an ethic based on a formal pragmatic curriculum before teachers can similarly observe and thus learn from their mistakes and failings. The progressive elimination of such failings (however gradual), constitutes the most valuable source of praxial knowledge. The kind of progress that results from praxis, then, gives new meaning for an education that seeks to be “progressive” without on the other hand suffering from the typical criticisms usually attributed to that philosophical description.

Praxial knowledge is thus rooted in personal experience that, in turn, has been guided by informed judgments made in connection with ethical criteria that vary considerably according to the particulars of a situation. It simply cannot be passed on directly as recipes. It can only be shared in theoretical and indirect terms that need to be ‘practiced’ or ‘developed’ anew by other practitioners “in action” in terms of the criteria provided by an evolving phronesis that is itself guided by the ever-changing particulars of their different situations. Therefore, the knowledge-base at stake in “methods and techniques” courses, in methods books, and in research of various kinds, is not and should not be regarded as a fixed, final, objective, applied technology of “what works.” This knowledge should be recognized as being at best a theoretical starting point for developing praxial knowledge and professional competence through ever-improved praxial success, not as a techinicist collection of recipes and techniques that function as the “final word” as to “what works.” And finally, the relevant “diagnoses” or hypotheses required by any adaptive application of such theory to a particular praxial situation requires a functional background in developmental and educational psychology, philosophical dimensions of teaching and curriculum, and a functional sociological familiarity with how schooling is organized. Such foundations from supporting disciplines are basic in every way to the types of diagnosis, analysis, reflection and adaptive judgment required of a music teacher as a professional.

VI Critical Theory and Music Education

Critical Theory is a particular body of literature committed to a particular agenda of human freedom or empowerment; a particular way of analyzing and dealing with a wide range of social problems. Unlike many other philosophies and theories (such as postmodernism’s concern with linguistics and literary interpretation), most of the social issues addressed by Critical Theory have considerable relevance for schooling, education and teaching. It is not claimed here that Critical Theory alone can serve to reform and redirect music education. However, the increasing relevance John Dewey and other pragmatists have for Habermas puts the current literature of Critical Theory directly in touch with and relevant to current issues in education. Similarly, the importance to Critical Theory of the need for pragmatic strategies for social change — that is, the importance of not being just another theory that cannot be put into practice — recommends it as a basis for change agency in music education. Given its central concern with issues central to music and to schooling, and because it already serves as the basis of a growing body of educational philosophy and theory (much of which is unknown to music educators), Critical Theory provides an important component for professionalizing music education that cannot and should not continue to be overlooked.

Critical teaching is especially well-suited to serving as a basis for needed change in music education today. It requires teachers to remain current with regard to changing bases of research, theory and praxis and to engage regularly in ideology critique. In particular it requires systematic reflection upon teaching praxis where success is judged in terms of the benefits for students. This self-correcting feature prevents a Critical Theory-based teaching praxis from itself becoming an ideology and its self-critical spirit also prevents it from becoming part of the problem that it criticizes. In sum, to be professional in terms suggested by Critical Theory means a never-ending quest to insure and improve music teaching as a praxis for bringing about the “good results” of personal musical praxis on the part of students throughout their lives.

Teaching as praxis, then, also means teaching music for praxis — that is, for the purposes of using music as lifelong personal praxis. Seen from the curricular point of view, then, Critical Theory points to the importance of music itself as praxis: music’s value or “good” and thus its reason for being in the general education of all students is to be put into action to bring about pragmatic benefits of a kind that only it can contribute to the life well-lived. Music is thus not an abstract or inert “subject” or “discipline” studied in school; it exists to be put “into action” for its fullest potential in enhancing life.

In conclusion, teaching as praxis is guided by action ideals that judge success in terms of the musical benefits brought about by musical praxis — by music “in action” in the lives of students as a direct result of their musical schooling. Music in this view is an important and basic humanizing praxis because through it “human beings become human in coming to know themselves as human” (Wartofsky, 1979). Teaching music is, therefore, doubly engaged as a praxis where curriculum as a theoretical and ideal claim comes “to life” musically for students to the degree that they can put music “into action” in their lives. Music education, then, is action for a change in the musical lives of students now and in the future as adults.

Five questions for Edwin Gordon and Bennett Reimer

[During the Philosophy of Music Education Symposium III [PME III] in Los Angeles [May 28-31, 1997] a “dialog” was held between Edwin Gordon and Bennett Reimer and the remaining participants in the Symposium. Harold Fiske served as moderator. Five groups of questions were prepared by Fiske; these questions guided the course of the discussion. Listed below are the questions. Anthony Palmer, who introduced the participants and organized and chaired PME III, invited general discussion based on Dr. Fiske’s questions and the responses to them by Drs. Gordon and Reimer.]

1. The methodology of doing philosophy

Does philosophy encompass all music education research or does its methodology distinguish and warrant its identity as a “special research interest group”?

  • Is all music research “philosophical”? For example, is the scientific method a philosophy or does philosophy transcend hypothesis testing? (Is science a philosophy or is philosophy a science?)
  • Does current music education philosophy reflect carefully applied methodology?
  • Should philosophy of music education derive essentially from a theory of music or can we rely on philosophies developed in other non musical disciplines to shape our own philosophy?
  • Is there irony in the sense that, while there is a good deal of criticism of 19th century aesthetics-based music education, there is still a tendency to rely on 17th-19th century philosophers for revising contemporary philosophy of music education?

2. The preparation of professional music education philosophers

Should any changes be made to graduate programs in order to nurture the development of future professional music education philosophers?

  • What non-music/non-music education philosophical sources/references should be considered required reading for graduate students?
  • What philosophical principles and criteria should guide curriculum development, evaluation and criticism?

3. Philosophy of music education and the problems of teaching music

What are the most critical problems in music education that need to be addressed by philosophers?

  • Is there a gap between philosophical research and the practitioner? If so, how should this gap be bridged?
  • What items should be included on a profession-wide research agenda that will predictably lead to better music teaching? [MayDay Group question*] (Is philosophy of music education important or are we just kidding ourselves?)
  • Is there a crisis in music education philosophy? If so, is it limited to the research community or does it affect the practitioner as well? Is a methodology war the cause of this crisis? If so, is it a “good” crisis or a “bad” one?
  • In what ways can music education philosophy affect the upgrading of music education materials and musical purpose?

4. The effects of music education philosophy on society

Are the effects of a philosophy of music education limited to music teaching or can they be made to affect as well our culture’s musical institutions (e.g., mass media, publishers, music business firms)? [modified MayDay Group question*]

  • How can philosophy of music education influence institutions so as to improve their contribution to raising the musical quality of social and cultural life? [modified MayDay Group question*]

5. Cultural bias effects on philosophical methodology

Is it possible for any research methodology (experimental, qualitative, historical, ethnographic, philosophical) to be culture free (vs. culture loaded)?

  • What standards of musicianship and musicality in music education can be guided by traditions associated with aesthetic theories, while still emphasizing the cultural and social situatedness of the music practices in question? [MayDay Group question*]